РефератыИностранный языкInIntegrating Care And Justice Moral Development Essay

Integrating Care And Justice Moral Development Essay

Integrating Care And Justice: Moral Development Essay, Research Paper


Part One:


The criticisms of Kohlberg’s moral development


stages seem to center around three major points, his research methods,


the “regression” of stage four, and finally his goals.


The first criticism that I would like to


address is that of his research methods. Kohlberg is often criticized for


not only his subject selection, but also the methods by which he tries


to extricate data from those subjects. His initial study consisted of school


boys from a private institution in Chicago. The problem with this is fairly


obvious, that this does not represent a significant portion of the population


to allow for generalized conclusions. In other words, how can we test some


boys from Chicago and ascertain that this is how all people develop worldwide?


I believe that the answer to this criticism


comes from the theory that it relates to. Kohlberg’s moral development


schema is highly dependent upon the idea that there are fundamental truths


that cannot be dismissed. These ideas are “in the ether”, wound into the


very fabric that constructs human nature. Granted, his descriptions of


the various stages also seem very dependent upon the surroundings and social


institutions that an individual would be subjected to. Yet these institutions


would be have to be built upon people, all of whom would share these ideological


truths. It seems fairly obvious that all people have undeniable needs,


survival and some group membership. Kohlberg’s stages are merely methods


by which one could fulfill these needs. For instance, Spartan societies


were adamant about maintaining the purity and strength of the civilization.


Citizens saw no wrong in exposing a sick or lame baby to the elements so


that it might die. Surely an act of cruelty today, but in that society,


a necessary evil The prosperity and wealth of the whole was of greater


importance than that of the individual.


In addition to these justifications, additional


research substantiated Kohlberg’s claims. Different subjects were tested,


from all ages and regions, and the same conclusions were drawn from the


data. Assuming that these conclusions are correct, and the data leads to


the same interpretation, is there any other possibility? This argument


seems most impressive, especially considering the differences between people


that are evident in everyday life. Similarities on such an abstract level


must be supportive of Kohlberg’s claims.


Another criticism of Kohlberg assumes that


his subjects are biased, but proposes that his methods are even worse.


To get the perspective of another person, he confronts them with seemingly


impossible, unrealistic, and confrontational dilemmas. I, myself, had trouble


with the Heinz dilemma because of my inability to believe that it was something


that could take place in the real world. Even more so, the situation was


something that was very foreign, and very hard to relate to. Anyone who


has contemplated something very life changing, like a death in the family,


then experienced it, understands how different it is to actually be faced


with the dilemma. When theorizing, it is hard to maintain the intimate


connection needed to truly react to a moral dilemma.


My defense of this situation comes from


a lack of a suitable alternative. True moral dilemmas are not only rare,


but extremely hard to document. When faced with a situation that demands


not only one’s complete attention, but emotional vigor, it is really hard


to find time to document or discuss feelings (let alone the motivation


to do so!). For example, looking at the Heinz dilemma, it would be very


hard to explain why one was chasing


a man around while he tried to find


a cure for his dying wife. An even less enticing alternative would be trying


to sit him down and discuss how he was feeling.


So, the only proper and effective way to


get a response is to propose a hypothetical situation, and document replies.


It may not elicit the pure data that one desires, but according to the


Heisenberg principle, it is impossible to measure anything without influencing


it. Some research methods indicate that it is more important to follow


one’s thoughts through the reasoning process, rather than just asking for


possible solutions. However, I have to believe, and justify from personal


experience, that people have incredibly low attention spans. Asking someone


to explain how they think through a decision is almost as likely to yield


useful data as asking them to volunteer their PIN numbers. It seems as


though people are able not only to be influenced, but to influence themselves


into making different decisions. This can lead to the “endless circle”


conversation.


The criticism that I find most interesting


is the supposed “regression” that occurs when going from stage three to


four. Personally, I must agree with the idea that it is, in fact, a priority


change. I also believe that this comes from my undeniable faith in the


“goodness” of humanity. I would like to believe that in their heart and


soul, everyone is good natured. So, to see that one must develop stage


four is disappointing.


Yet, I will agree that it is necessary.


It is a comprehensive step, and an improvement from the stage three point


of view. No matter how enticing and supposedly noble stage three appears,


it is lacking components necessary to promote the functionality of the


person who holds it. A loss of innocence is not necessarily a detriment,


especially when considering personal experience. Skin tends to thicken


as one gets older. Therefore, is it necessarily a regression that someone


would tend to trust others less, and be more interested maintaining social


institutions?


I believe that this in no way represents


a regression, but rather a broadened scope and interpretation of surroundings.


At level three, you are totally interested in fulfilling the obligations


that are expected of you. The world seems a very small place, one person


and your surroundings, people, places, and things. If the requirements


that are expected from day to day, from people who are very close to you


can be fulfilled, that is the absolute goal. As one grows older, you are


exposed to more of the institutions and methods that are integral to the


relationship and interaction of all people. The rules have changed. There


are more requirements, more expected of you. Unfortunately, every person


does not have limitless resources with which to meet all of these goals.


So, priorities must change. New social institutions now appear to be the


driving force in happiness and security. So, they now encompass all the


priorities that drove a person at stage three. To fulfill the previous


stage’s goals with this new scope, one must dedicate resources to it.


Finally, I would like to discuss Kohlberg’s


point of view when considering what I call his “goals”. Some have criticized


that Kohlberg is trying to objectify morality to a Natural Law, or justice


perspective. Although he does seem to abstract characteristics to a societal


level, I do not believe that his is an honest attempt to undermine the


gathered data integrity. In other words, although it seems he is drawing


the same conclusions over and over, he is not distorting it to do so.


Kohlberg is often criticized for a libertarian


ideological bias in his conclusions of gathered data. In addition, it has


been observed that his conclusions are carefully explained, argued and


defended, but they can be twisted and contorted to fit any range of different


opinions. They mandate an agreement to social contract, that being used


as a philosophical base from which moral guidelines are built. But social


systems differ from region to region, and within regions by people.


I believe that the criticisms themselves


do not harm Kohlberg’s views, but rather enforce them. As I have discussed


before, there are undeniable personal needs that every individual works


to fulfill, regardless of stated motives. Everyone needs to survive, and


to be emotionally fulfilled by belonging. The systems by which people administer


their interaction are simply tools by which they meet those needs. However,


I have also said that I have a flawless devotion to the goodness of mankind.


Thereby, I believe that people are trying to better their situation relative


to one another and the situation of society as a whole. Kohlberg may view


these moral ideals as too socially interactive, but isn’t that what the


true goal of any of this is? People truly feel good when they have met


their desires, and one of those is to exist with other people in a cohesive


social system. As unbelievable as it may sound, Kohlberg’s findings do


not represent distorted data, but rather the incredible coincidence that


all people, on some level, are inherently similar.


It would be unfair to try to enforce the


ideas that come with Kohlbergian justice without also defending Carol Gilligan’s


theme of caring. Therefore, I would like to address three criticisms: the


paradox of self-care, the idea that care is a regressive movement, and


finally, the seemingly huge jump from stage one to two.


I personally find the self-care characteristic


of caring to be the most interesting to discuss. During class sessions,


everyone seemed most interested with this perspective. It seems as though


it is the ethical issue that plagues society. Where does the balance lie


between seeking to fulfill one’s own interests, and meeting the requirements


placed upon one by others? I believe that we all recognize a need to initialize


and solidify a healthy caring for oneself before it is possible to be outwardly


caring for others.


However, the way that this method is proposed


makes it appear as though it might be a cop-out.


My perspective comes from the fact that


there is no really appropriate way to show self-care without seeming self-centered.


No matter how little one dedicates to oneself, no matter what the circumstances,


someone will see it as too much. Yet, there is no effective way to show


compassion, respect, or contentment with the outside world without first


developing all of these attributes within oneself. When constructing this


self-persona, the goal is not to become conceited, but rather to develop


a foundation upon which more complex interactions can be constructed. Of


course, any well intentioned act can be construed into something that it


is not. I truly believe that this is the case when critiquing self-care.


I would also like to argue that self-care


as a whole is not what it seems to be, nor is it what it’s name implies.


Rather, it is a competence at a certain level personal and societal development.


At earlier times in one’s life, the easiest way to contribute to surroundings


is to not harm them. For instance, it would not be expected of a toddler


to assist in the preparation of dinner. The best that he could hope to


do is not destroy anything! At this level of development adequacy is defined


by not harming something, not necessarily working towards it’s betterment.


So, caring for oneself is not self-centered at all, it is the best method


available. By caring for oneself, you are bettering your personal situation.


In turn, this improves the quality of not only your life, but those around


you. You are more presentable, easier to associate with, and more productive.


With my previous point in mind, I would


like to move onto the idea that the levels of caring are actually a regression


from previous stages. This assumption comes from comparisons of Kohlbergian


stage three attributes, with that of Gilligan’s care stages. Stage three


(Kohlberg) seems to represent the “Prince Valiant” of personalities. One


should work towards becoming a better person, fulfill societal requirements,


forgive transgressions, and exhibit constant unadulterated pacifism. It


truly seems to be a noble individual, the likes of which exist only in


fairy tales and fantasy novels. Stage one of caring then comes along, representing


a more introspective, self-interested individual. This new person is very


afraid of hurt from others, and does everything within his/her power to


avoid it. In fact, this includes not reaching out to others in any way,


so that there is no chance of being scarred.


It seems as though this is an almost childish,


selfish response to harsh reality. But reality is the point! Reality does


not allow for Prince Valiant to be effective. Instead, he is abused, stepped


on, and taken for granted. These are not exactly prime rewards for someone


who is dedicated to being a good person and helping others. However, this


raises a conflicting point, when we now consider that society’s mistreatment


of people leads them to lose their faith. So all people must be inherently


abusive, right? I should hope not, but rather, that it is a case of poor


timing. Granted, there will be cases where people are, in fact, not “role


models”. They will be non-supportive, destructive, and frustrating. From


personal experience (and thereby bias), I find that most people are not


evil, but just not at the same stage. Everyone can remember back to grammar


and middle school, where children are not only non-supportive, but cruel


and incredibly hurtful. As they grow older, these characteristics disappear.


In the meantime, however, they are busy dismantling the naïve nobility


of stage three. If, somehow, all people could be raised to the same levels


at the same time, there is a chance we would never see the desensitizing


that we do. So, it is not a regression, but a move forward, a better ability


to deal with the real world.


Finally, one of the biggest critiques of


the caring system is the difference between the first and second stages.


While stage one has been criticized for being a regression, stage two has


been attacked for being a quantum leap from stage one. The morals and guiding


themes of stage two are so diametrically different from that of stage one,


that it seems almost an impossible move. Also, there is an argument that


stage two admits that stage one was a regression, stage two merely brings


us back up to par.


Stage two, admittedly, is a huge step in


personal thinking. Instead of the self-centered, protective nature of stage


one, stage two is predicated on self-sacrifice, maternal instincts, and


maintaining peace. To me, this is not a step back up to a stage that was


lost during a stage one regression, but an incredibly comprehensive step


forward. The key is that this stage does not even attack the same issues


in a similar way. Rather, it depends upon using oneself as a tool to show


interest and caring for others. In terms of conflicting views, this could


be the most impressive point towards unifying them. Some view this entire


stage as a complete change of heart, throwing out all ideals and starting


anew. Instead of looking at it with the previous stage’s perspective, the


way to attack this is to recognize that this way of thinking is an entirely


new strategy.


(The next section is assuming that one


would naturally move from a Kohlbergian stage three to Gilligan’s stage


one). Stage three was nice, but too nice. It allowed too many opportunities


for those who did not share stage three to abuse someone who does. It was


obviously inadequate. So, instead of rashly charging into a different mindset,


one takes time to “rebuild the foundation” (Gilligan stage one). With a


new base to build upon, one can put together another plan of attack. Those


undeniable human goals are still there, it is just a matter of coming up


with a good system to accomplish them.


At stage two, with the scars of inefficient


methods still showing, one can try to develop a new system that is comparable


to all previous attempts, but slightly better. If hurt significantly by


stage three’s inability to deal with conflict, caring stage two may not


come about until much later. Stage one is a healing process that leads


to a new outlook, and a greater ability to deal with the problems that


plagued stage three. It seems silly to assume that people dev

elop by trial


and error, but I would like to meet the person who hasn’t! Everyone makes


bad decisions, then tries to make sure that those events do not repeat


themselves. This idea is integral to the stage two leap.


Part Two: Integration of Care and Justice


The major point of this part of the paper


is to hypothesize and analyze Kohlberg’s stage three and four, along with


the transition between the two. From what I have gathered from the assignment,


the goal is to reanalyze both the stages, show their adequacies and inadequacies,


then integrate the two to form a stronger quasi-stage four. I have discussed


the stage three to four “regression” in the first part of my paper, but


this segment will be more dedicated to the integration of the stage’s details,


rather than the blatant defense of the perspective.


My first job will be to show stage three’s


adequacies. Stage three is a personification of what we all wish we could


be. Noble, strong, and almost saintly, it represents all of the qualities


that everyone wants to possess. The stage is almost entirely based upon


the idea that all people deserve to be treated with respect and dignity,


regardless of the previous actions, or outward complexion. I find that


the word “faith” seems the best to describe this stage. Faith in people


around you, and in their motives.


However, some of the shortfalls of stage


three are very aptly listed in the handout packet. It can be indeterminate,


arbitrary, idealistic, indecisive, and localized. Indeterminacy has it’s


root in the enactment of the “golden rule”. It seems so simple and easy


to discuss, but in practice, it’s execution is questionable. “Do unto others


as you would wish them to do to you.” But why does that indicate that it


is the right choice? Isn’t it a matter of personal preference? Suppose


I enjoy being beaten with a bat! Does that give me the right to do it to


someone else? This rule assumes that all people share the same interests,


likes, and dislikes. If the entire population has an aversion to physical


harm, then this rule will work. However, can’t an assailant justify his


actions by proving that he enjoys physical harm? Although morally enticing,


the golden rule does not set down concrete guidelines that should mold


people’s behavior.


Localization and the in-group also propose


a significant criticism of this view. Stage three almost mandates that


those people who surround you are the most important in the world. One


should fulfill their obligations to the in-group above and beyond all others.


In other words, you must desensitize yourself to the rest of the world’s


problems, and just deal with those that involve your direct family. How


in the world can this be considered a moral competence? You are selecting


those people for whom you will show compassion and caring, and excluding


others by rule. Unfortunately, stage three has no allowance for integrating


the social contract into moral development. Instead, it totally excludes


it with this in-group system.


To close this point, I would like to raise


the hypothesis that stage three is theoretically the best stage that can


be achieved. It assumes that people are moral by nature, and with a little


guidance, can show this in their treatment of others. The assumption is


made that regardless of perspective, there are undeniable rights and respects


that every human deserves. No matter what the priorities of each individual,


they will not infringe upon the rights of others. However, in practice


it is simply not effective. Based upon the competence achieved up until


the stage three level, it seems the best policy of interaction. But in


practice, it stinks!. It just does not function on a level that would allow


it to be the predominant


method for interpersonal relations and ethical


decision-making. The system is based upon trust and values, neither of


which people tend to put much faith into.


Stage four remedies many of the stage three


inadequacies with the introduction and assimilation of a social contract.


Many of the same ideas from stage three remain, given new functionality


and definition. For instance, the golden rule has been replaced with social


reciprocity, the idea that merit is given to good citizens. The social


system itself takes over as the primary guiding focus of the people.


Because of this new agreed upon social


contract, the holes of stage three have been filled. There is no longer


the indecisive, abstract nature of the previous stage, because a contract


has been agreed upon by the masses. Not every little niche of the policy


agrees with every person, but for the most part, it holds the beliefs of


the population. A certain “golden rule” has been put into place, with designated


actions that warrant punishment. If you do this, you will be punished accordingly.


There is no chance for arbitration (although one is able to change the


system itself, or prove their innocence through the proper channels). Rules


have been set down, agreed upon, and now enforced.


At the same time, the localization of stage


three has also been removed. The system that works to enforce this “new


golden rule” has to be agreed upon by all people. It’s flavor may change


slightly from region to region, but generally, they must all follow the


same guidelines. So, just to achieve stage four we must banish the localization


of stage three. Personal priorities then follow the system. Instead of


prioritizing the in-group above all others, a new conglomerate is formed


of everyone’s in-groups into one society. The survival of that society


is supreme, since it is the chosen protector of all these familial microcosms.


Laws, rules and regulations take over for individualistic judgement, helping


to herd everyone into the proper behavior.


With this new system, we obviously lose


some of the aspects of stage three that were most attractive. We no longer


have the family dedicated, honor above-all-else person that we did in the


previous stage. He has been replaced with someone who is now, at best,


a law abiding citizen. The principles of stage three have been incorporated,


though not fully, into the pragmatism of stage four. For instance, a lawless


or unconventional act that would not have been tolerated at stage three


would be ignored at stage four so that the integrity of the social system


would not be compromised. We lose the hardcore justice orientation, and


replace it with a more flexible society-inclusive system.


Increasing the size of anything to encompass


more increases it’s complexity. Complexity means that this system is not


only hard to maintain, but increasingly slow to acquiesce to the changing


needs of the people. It takes a lot of time to change an entire society’s


interpretations. Status-quo stagnation occurs very quickly, and reform


seemingly takes forever.


So, imagine that we could take stage four,


plop in into a blender, add some stage three, and come out with an even


better system. What would we do? This is the next question to be addressed.


Looking at stage three’s and stage four’s adequacies and areas of lacking,


we need to incorporate pieces of both into an entirely new system.


The real goal is to somehow take stage


three’s interpersonal nobility and faith, and give them to a stage four


person. At the same time, we do not want to undermine the societal interactiveness


of stage four! I believe that what we end up with is the theoretical model


of a democracy. For instance, we take stage four’s society agreed upon


contract (assuming that it is somewhat noble, as opposed to something from


the Third Reich). We now assume that an act has been committed that borders


between criminality and unconventionalism. How could we approach this?


Stage three says: “If it isn’t a threat to my immediate person, or those


who surround me, then don’t worry about it.” Stage four would reply: “What


of it’s effect on the social system, is it against the law?” What we really


need to do is combine the two perspectives. If this act is first viewed


to warrant public action (an arrest, trial, or hearing), then that should


be the course of action. It is what takes place next that is very important.


During the proceedings, each and every person must come to terms with it


in their own way. They must decide if it is destructive, constructive,


or indifferent. As a group, they must decide on the best course of action.


This way we have incorporated the individualistic judgement and nobility


of each person and fused it with societal administration. In addition,


we have allowed each person to place part of their own golden rule interpretation


into the system.


By carefully combining the features of


two very different stages, we have come up with a system that is better


suited to meeting the needs of a population. Unfortunately, it was invented


hundreds of years ago, and implemented in the United States Constitution.


Granted, it does not work perfectly, but it seems a suitable compromise


when considering the alternatives. It may be a slow process, and one that


can be abused to fit one’s needs, but it is the only one that incorporates


the individual into the molding of the system.


The final part of this paper will be dedicated


to the combination of two very different arenas of thought, the moral development


paths of justice and care. Some have argued for and against each, some


have argued for and against both. What we will try to do is to build an


entirely new moral system on the strengths of these two. Theoretically,


we should come up with a super-competent solution, one that is better than


the two individually. Rather than try to develop this step by step and


point by point (which would be intolerable after about the second line),


I’d like to just give my interpretation of what the final product would


look like. One note: the most that can be possibly asked of any person


in any system is that they give 100 percent all the time. Therefore, any


theorizing that we do is subject to the fact that people only have the


resources to accomplish certain things.


To combine the best features of two diametrically


different institutions of thought we have to first identify what those


features are. Kohlbergian justice is the pragmatic, society oriented variety


that is admittedly dedicated to preserving social systems. Gilligan’s caring


is predicated on good interaction between people. Although they sound like


they might be trying to achieve the same things, they are going at it in


two separate ways. Kohlberg wants to invent a system by which all people


know what is expected of them. Rules are proposed, agreed upon, set down,


and enforced. Each and every person knows what is appropriate behavior.


Even at stage five, the supposed highest known stage of Kohlberg’s development,


the society rates very high. There may be different ways to approach running


a society, but there is no question that there must be something running


it.


Gilligan seems to agree that people need


rules by which they can relate to one another. However, she seems to delve


deeper into the actual motivations of those rules. While obeying the regulations


of society, you must also show some sort of compassion and caring for other


people. As a trivial example, Kohlberg’s system would say that it was rude


to interrupt someone who is speaking. Gilligan would say that merely not


interrupting is not adequate. Instead, you must show interest in what that


person is trying to say. You must somehow relate with the speaker on some


level. In doing so, you not only draw more from his words, but you show


that you can identify with him.


Another feature of Gilligan’s work that


I feel should be integrated into the justice theme is that of self-care.


When put down in words it seems somewhat egotistical and self-centered.


Kohlberg would be interested in self-care only if it contributed to maintaining


society. But balancing the needs of the many, and the needs of the few


is the hardest part about effectively administering any group of people.


Some individuals will have very menial needs, others will say they require


luxuries. The key is to provide a method by which all people can fulfill


those needs. Self-care will differ significantly between even similar people.


So, rather than trying to meet their needs outright, it is better to just


provide a chance by which they can provide for themselves. Thus achieving


a balance between self-care and still allotted care for others. (I know,


I’m drawing the democracy parallelism again, sorry!)


Kohlberg provides us with the minimal framework


by which regulations maintain the necessities of people. If his guidelines


are followed, it can be said that everyone who lives by them will be at


least partially satisfied. Gilligan, on the other hand, shows us that there


is a much deeper level to which we can all aspire. Putting effort into


everyday interaction, from talking to listening, can greatly enhance every


experience. In doing so, we are not only improving the quality of our own


lives, but also the lives of those we interact with.


Another aspect of caring that I would like


to bring into the “justice world” is included in level three, the highest


level of caring. It states that there are absolutely no black or white


issues. What might be correct for one person, is not necessarily the same


for another. This would fill a huge hole in the Kohlberg moral development


system. Justice is largely criticized because it “forces” everyone into


a social group. It then slaps some rules down, and expects that they are


applicable to everyone. Gilligan states that this is not true, but rather,


everything is a shade of gray. Be careful though! This does not mean that


rules are now not applicable to anyone. Rather, it states that we must


use our judgement when considering transgressions of the law. There may


be special circumstances that need to be addressed.


Finally, Kohlberg’s critics have said that


stage five is too arbitrary. It is not easy to tell exactly how much one


owes to the social contract, or what to do with people who do not necessarily


agree with it. Gilligan would argue that there is a way to resolve this


conflict of interests through dialogue, attention, and compromise. Where


Kohlberg’s system leave opportunity for arbitration, Gilligan’s says that


there is no need. Instead of giving people a hard set of rules to live


by, or demanding their surrender to a contract, we could talk to them individually


and address the situation.


At the same time, justice maintains that


there are undeniable rules that must be obeyed. So, we are combining the


best of both worlds. Using Kohlberg’s justice orientation, we are guaranteeing


the sanctity of all those who have already agreed to the social contract.


Concurrently, we’re taking it upon ourselves to listen to a non-supportive


person, and possibly come to a small compromise to fit their needs.


In conclusion, it seems that there is definitely


a way to combine the Kohlberg justice theme and the Gilligan caring theme


of moral development. Mr. Kohlberg provides a method to police a society


that does not include 100 percent utopian citizens. Ms. Gilligan gives


us the ability to relate to each and every person, as a person. She indicates


ways that we can identify with their perspectives, understand their needs,


and compromise. Although the real world seems infinitely more complex than


either of these models, they bear a frightening resemblance to real societies


and real people. Maybe someday, a perfect model will be constructed, judged


by a perfect path of moral development. Until then, I hope that I have


found a good combination of these two ideas.


One last side note: I think I could spend


weeks typing a paper on this subject. There are thousands of facets of


each system that could fit into the other’s potential flaws. However, I


think I’ve been long-winded enough as it is. I have tried to make my points


as succinct and reasonable as possible, but without sacrificing exactly


what I wanted to say. Thank you for your patience.

Сохранить в соц. сетях:
Обсуждение:
comments powered by Disqus

Название реферата: Integrating Care And Justice Moral Development Essay

Слов:5861
Символов:38659
Размер:75.51 Кб.