РефератыИностранный языкPhPhilosophical Foundations Of Poverty And Distribution Essay

Philosophical Foundations Of Poverty And Distribution Essay

, Research Paper


Any Lockeian scholar would be lying if they told you that any topic in


the secondary literature on the Two Treatises of Government was more famous (or


infamousÉdepending on who you talk to), widely debated, or caused more


controversy than the old Oxford gradÕs theory of property. Some are shouting


from the left that Locke argues a rights claim for subsistence for all


individuals, that it may even support MarxÕs theory of exploitation. Yelling


back are those from the right who claim that he formulates a moral


justification for capitalist appropriation of property. Then of course there


are those somewhere in between who are telling everyone to shut up because


Locke wrote the damn thing over three hundred years ago in the political


context of 17th century England and to derive these kinds of modern political


presumptions is ludicrous. They all make fine cases for their respective


theories. This humble treatise, however, will merely essay to provide a fairly


objective explanation of John LockeÕs disputed offering to the political and


economic understanding of property and how it relates to poverty and the


distribution of wealth. It will then continue to examine the two most


preeminent, contemporary champions of welfarist and entitlement theories in


that of John Rawls and Robert Nozick respectively, focusing specifically on


what they, standing on LockeÕs shoulders, offer as an acceptable system of


economic justice.


Locke begins by stating that each person has a natural right to preserve his or


her life. "God has given the Earth to all people in common for their


sustenance." (Locke 310). In the state of nature, each person owns everything


in nature equally with everyone else. However, some things in nature must be


"appropriated" in order for one to derive any sustaining benefit from them. As


an example, Locke says one must take possession of acorns or apples in order to


eat them and, so, derive sustenance from them. But one must do something


positive in order to appropriate the acorns or apples and, thus, make them


one’s own. A person possesses his or her own body and the actions of that body.


One owns oneself. By virtue of exercising the labor of one’s body in


conjunction with the machinations of nature on land held in common by mankind,


one removes a thing from the state of nature and makes it one’s own. Locke says


that one’s labors puts a "distinction" between oneself and the rest of mankind


in relation to the object of one’s labors. The rights of the individual as


expressed in one’s labors creates private rights.


Ownership comes out of the appropriation of land and the mixing of labor into


the appropriated land. This originates in the state of nature where there is no


government above the individual to impede their efforts to use and hold onto


their property nor regulate trade between buyers and sellers. Natural freedom,


according to Locke, is to live within the bounds of natural law (reason) which


are respected in the state of nature as the right to enjoy the product of one’s


labor and protect its use.


This does not mean, however, that every person has a right to remove from


nature everything that he or she wills. There are limits to what may be


appropriated from nature. First, something may be appropriated from nature so


long as it is enjoyed. Next, one may appropriate to the point of spoilage or


destruction. It is a limit because the properties that were spoiled or


destroyed should have remained common property. As common property, another


person could have mixed his or her labors with nature, thus taking it his or


her property.


In terms of land, one takes possession of land by improving it. It is owned to


the extent that one can manage the land and use its products, and is subject to


the same limitations as the other things one can appropriate from nature


through his labors. God has commanded that it be so to the extent that He


commanded mankind to labor over the earth. And regardless of one’s


appropriation of land, there is so much land left in common that the affect of


appropriating the land is negligible. Indeed, when one cultivates his land, one


increases the "common stock" of mankind by creating an abundance of product,


when compared to leaving the same land to nature. Thus any amount that is


cultivated beyond one’s needs can be used to supply the needs of others. That


portion of one’s lands which produces the surplus remains somewhat in the


possession of the rest of mankind. The rest of mankind benefit’s from the


abundance produced through labor.


Civic freedom in the political society transfers only the right of property


protection to the government, the executive power of individuals becomes the


government’s duty to punish transgressions of natural law. Civil rights, argues


Locke, are not the restriction of the liberties of private property but the


consent of individuals to this duty of government to be the judge and executor


of civil law founded upon principles of reason. Property rights are passed on


from the state of nature to the political state. John Locke demands that the


government which is instituted by the political society is assigned with the


power and purpose to regulate and protect the use of property. He argues that


people are not "naturally subject" to any human government but introduces the


consent of the governed concept.


The people, however, have the natural liberty at all time to revoke their


trust in the government, should it unjustly intrude on their property rights,


equality, or other freedoms. But Locke clearly articulates this breaking of


trust in a government is not a return to the state of nature but to the


political society (which then creates a new government). During this upheaval


the natural right of individuals to own and use private property is maintained;


the "artificial" government is what changes.


Locke does believe that this human government will be uncorrupted as it was


mentioned earlier that "perfect freedom" is an ideal for imperfect beings. The


social contract, in the form of Locke’s political society, is primarily meant


to secure individual freedom. Whether it binds together a group of people with


a national myth or social identity seems to be a secondary benefit of the


political society. Locke intends for the distinct members of the newly formed


civil state to be served by their government, not serve the personal interests


of the leaders. It is interesting that the method Locke prescribes for choosing


the form of government is a majority vote among the political society’s members


but that form of government is not necessarily representative democracy. Once


the form of government is decided then the people place their trust in whatever


it is, revocable by the citizens should it interfere in their civic liberties


and private property. The political society formed out of the individuals and


not the government would be the social identity of Locke’s state. The


government can be replaced by the permanent political society.


Without private property rights to be protected it could be possible to


guarantee individual freedom for everyone to appropriate as much as they


please. But Locke points out that property accumulation is limited, not by


intruders, by the factors of spoilage and individual labor strength (not


necessarily intruders). Labor not only defines the individual as owner of


property but also defines how much of the property can be appropriated. The


property is meant to be enjoyed by the owner to the maximum; only as much


property that can be used without surplus spoiling is the other limitation of


accumulation.


Locke’s detailed discussion in Chapter V outlines the impact of money in


reducing and eliminating these limitations by exploiting the so-called surplus


value and wage-labor to maximize profits. It is most important for Locke that


this productive activity is free from intrusion by other individuals in the


state of nature and the government in the civil state.


There is no individual freedom unless property rights are established and


property protection is enforced. Modern-day critics label these statements as


justification of uncontrolled, industrialized capitalism and exploitation of


the labor working class. "[Some scholars feel] that LockeÕs theory indirectly


inspired Karl MarxÕs theory of exploitation" (Yolton 90). Some thinkers like


Marx actively participated in organizations with the goal of bringing down


liberal, capitalist states. Yet today documents like the American constitution,


embody principles such as consent of the governed, inalienable rights, and


protection of property. Individual freedom is meaningless without private


property in both the "non-governmental", theoretical state of nature and


political societies such as the United States which are modeled on liberal


ideas espoused by Locke. Finally, though the natural and political states are


founded on reason as revealed by the divine will Locke does not propose


theocracy but the right of members of the civic state to choose whatever form


of government they want.


Locke’s view of property accepts and endorses two states of affairs we find


problematic today. Huge differentials in wealth between the rich and the poor.


Locke essentially claims that the advent of money made it possible to


accumulate vast wealth. When wealth was measured in goods that were perishable,


this meant that there was a limit to what could be accumulated and kept. For


Locke, it is unjust to hoard those things which will simply perish uselessly


and since money is something lasting, it can be hoarded without any problem.


But as Locke continues, if a person exchanges his perishables for something


durable, such as money, then if, he invaded not the right of others, he might


heap up as much of these durab

le things as he pleased; the exceeding of the


bounds of his just Property not lying in the largeness of his possession, but


the perishing of any thing uselessly in it. This view is taken up in


contemporary theories of justice by libertarians such as Robert Nozick which


will be examined later. (Regan Class Notes).


After acquiring goods of a particular kind there must be enough, and as good


left in common for others. We must take only what we can use to prevent


spoiling and waste. Locke makes it clear that there is always a right of


subsistence that can be evoked be the poverty stricken. Furthermore, Locke


insists that those who own property have a duty to the needy. The holding of


property carries certain duties and the central one is that the holder creates


wealth that will benefit the common good. Locke holds a doctrine of communal


rights – often called "use rights" and "claim rights." This is found in the


notion of common or public land which is used by everyone in the society. So he


recognizes the need for both private property and common land.


Locke sees private property as essential for the development of a productive


modern economy, one which will vastly increase the wealth of the society so


that everyone in it benefits. Locke is not celebrating private wealth as a good


in itself but rather as a means to make society wealthier which in turn


improves the lives of everyone in the society. Enclosed land, when it becomes


private property, yields ten times what it would yield as common land. Locke


sees the right to property as grounded in a person’s ability to make this land


productive. By property Locke means more than just material goods. He means the


rights we have that others have a duty to recognize.


Locke’s thought on political legitimacy and property have had enormous


influence on contemporary political philosophy and his ideas have become part


of the public political culture of democratic societies. Despite his mistakes


and prejudices, he offered an account of how political power ought to be


constrained, making way for the justification of modern democratic societies we


find so ascendant todayÉand their critics. This brings us to the Rawlsian and


Nozickian take on the matter.


There are many theories of distributive justice. A detailed discussion of all


such theories is beyond the scope of this essay. For our purposes, it is


sufficient to explore the differences between entitlement and welfarist


theories of distributive justice. Under entitlement theories, a person deserves


goods because of some action the person has taken or some trait the person


possesses. One entitlement theory is the notion, sometimes associated with John


Locke, that a person has a right to what he produces. A modern variant, offered


by Robert Nozick in Anarchy, State and Utopia, states that a person is entitled


to those goods acquired in uncoerced exchanges with others.


In his famous, controversial work Nozick adopts a theory of property rights


under


which a person has a right to property if he acquired it in accordance with the


principle of "justice in acquisition" or in accordance with the principle of


"justice in transfer" from someone else who was entitled to it. Nozick attempts


to distinguish his theory from desert theories that judge the goodness of the


world according to whether the distribution of goods is consistent with a


person’s endowment with some quality. Instead, Nozick


evaluates the justice of a person’s property holdings solely according to the


method by which such holdings were acquired. Thus Nozick rejects theories of


distribution of the form "To each according to his X" as consequentialist and


ahistorical rather than process-based.


Welfarist theories of distributive justice, on the other hand, judge the


goodness of social states solely by the welfare or utility enjoyed by the


individuals in those states. Perhaps the two best known welfarist theories are


utilitarianism, which judges the welfare of a society according to the


unweighted sum of the utilities of its individual members, and the "leximin,"


based loosely upon the philosophy of John Rawls, which judges the welfare of a


society according to the well-being of its least well off member. Lying between


utilitarianism and the leximin with respect to preference for equality are


weighted utility theories that, like utilitarianism, consider the welfare of


each individual in determining social welfare, but that give greater weight to


the well-being of the less well off members of society.


The leximin is derived from the second of Rawls’ two principles of


justice, which maintains that society should be structured so as to maximize


the amount of primary goods held by the least well off class. This principle is


to guide societal structure only after society has implemented Rawls’ first


principle of justice, which calls for the maximization of the liberty of each


individual, consistent with the preservation of a like amount of liberty for


others. The welfarist leximin, unlike Rawls’ theory, maximizes the welfare, not


the primary goods, enjoyed by the worst off individual and considers the


distribution of liberty only as it affects the level of welfare.


Under a leximin, if the least well off individuals in two societies are equally


well off, the societies are judged by the welfare of the second least well off


individual and so on. If only the welfare of the least well off individuals are


considered, then the term "maximin" is used rather than leximin.


Although concern for incentive and demoralization effects may lead some


welfarist theories to consider how individuals acquired goods in determining


distribution, the fundamental focus of welfarist theories is often thought to


be at odds with that of entitlement theories. Under entitlement theories and


certain other non-welfarist theories, an individual has a right to a good


regardless of whether her ownership of the good is consistent with the welfare


of others or even with her own welfare. For example, according to Nozick, a


person who acquires a good in a just manner would have a right to the good even


if it were of little or no value to her and of enormous value to others.


In contrast, welfarist theories consider the fact that a person has created a


good only to the extent that allocating goods to their creators improves social


welfare by encouraging production or stability. The creator would not, however,


have a claim to the good derived solely from the act of creation. Thus,


welfarist theories of distributive justice permit taxation either to finance


public goods or to redistribute income, if the well-being of individuals in the


society is thereby improved.


An understanding of the implications of welfarist theories of distributive


justice for the tax structure should be understood. We focus on welfarist


rather than entitlement theories, in part because we believe that such ethics,


while not without problems, have more to commend them. It seems plausible, at


least, to judge government policies by the impact those policies have on the


welfare of the individuals in the society.


One particularly attractive feature of a welfarist analysis of taxation is its


responsiveness to the efficiency effects of various tax structures –effects


that nearly everyone finds relevant. Welfarist theories view as desirable any


change that makes some member of society better off without making any other


member worse off. Entitlement theories, on the other hand, may not endorse a


tax that increases the welfare of an "undeserving" individual even if that


change does not reduce the welfare of any other person. While it may be


possible to formulate a coherent ethical theory that rejects the this,


acceptance of this principle is frequently considered a prerequisite of any


acceptable social decision making rule.


A final reason for othe focus on welfarist theories is that entitlement


theories do not clearly justify any rate structure. Any tax imposed on an


unwilling taxpayer may be inconsistent with a system based on the view that a


person has a right to what he produces. Under such an entitlement theory, a


state might be permitted only to levy taxes that lead to making every member of


the society as well off or better off than she was before the tax. For example,


compulsory taxation might be justified to maintain a government strong enough


to protect the rights of the individuals living under it. Even if this notion


is accepted, however, it provides little guidance as to the appropriate rate


structure. The tax implications of welfarist ethics have been explored in the


important economics literature on "optimal taxation."


Welfarist ethics are not without their own difficulties, however. Many reject


such theories because they do not value rights except to the extent that they


improve the welfare of individuals. Others find the interpersonal comparisons


of utility required by welfarist theories to be not only difficult to make, as


most supporters of welfarism would admit, but also meaningless.


The rejection of an exclusively welfarist ethic does not necessarily imply


acceptance of an ethic that is exclusively entitlement-based. Conceivably, a


just society could consider both the welfare of individuals and entitlements in


determining a fair system of distribution. Optimal taxation analysis should be


of interest to those who believe in a mixed ethic, since it provides insight


into the tax structure inspired by any theory of distributive justice that is


at least partly concerned with individual welfare. Ultimately it is the duty of


society to see how the redistributive features of various progressive rate


structures comport with a wide variety of welfarist ethics, ranging from


utilitarianism to the Rawlsian leximin, in order to discover the best structure


for the society in which we live.


371

Сохранить в соц. сетях:
Обсуждение:
comments powered by Disqus

Название реферата: Philosophical Foundations Of Poverty And Distribution Essay

Слов:3484
Символов:23658
Размер:46.21 Кб.