РефератыИностранный языкDeDescarte 2 Essay Research Paper DescartesHow does

Descarte 2 Essay Research Paper DescartesHow does

Descarte 2 Essay, Research Paper


Descartes


How does Descartes try to extricate himself from the sceptical


doubts that he has raised? Does he succeed?


by Tom Nuttall


[All page references and quotations from the Meditations are


taken from the 1995 Everyman edition]


In the Meditations, Descartes embarks upon what Bernard Williams


has called the project of ‘Pure Enquiry’ to discover certain,


indubitable foundations for knowledge. By subjecting everything


to doubt Descartes hoped to discover whatever was immune to it.


In order to best understand how and why Descartes builds his


epistemological system up from his foundations in the way that he


does, it is helpful to gain an understanding of the intellectual


background of the 17th century that provided the motivation for


his work.


We can discern three distinct influences on Descartes, three


conflicting world-views that fought for prominence in his day.


The first was what remained of the mediaeval scholastic


philosophy, largely based on Aristotelian science and Christian


theology. Descartes had been taught according to this outlook


during his time at the Jesuit college La Flech_ and it had an


important influence on his work, as we shall see later. The


second was the scepticism that had made a sudden impact on the


intellectual world, mainly as a reaction to the scholastic


outlook. This scepticism was strongly influenced by the work of


the Pyrrhonians as handed down from antiquity by Sextus


Empiricus, which claimed that, as there is never a reason to


believe p that is better than a reason not to believe p, we


should forget about trying to discover the nature of reality and


live by appearance alone. This attitude was best exemplified in


the work of Michel de Montaigne, who mockingly dismissed the


attempts of theologians and scientists to understand the nature


of God and the universe respectively. Descartes felt the force of


sceptical arguments and, while not being sceptically disposed


himself, came to believe that scepticism towards knowledge was


the best way to discover what is certain: by applying sceptical


doubt to all our beliefs, we can discover which of them are


indubitable, and thus form an adequate foundation for knowledge.


The third world-view resulted largely from the work of the new


scientists; Galileo, Copernicus, Bacon et al. Science had finally


begun to assert itself and shake off its dated Aristotelian


prejudices. Coherent theories about the world and its place in


the universe were being constructed and many of those who were


aware of this work became very optimistic about the influence it


could have. Descartes was a child of the scientific revolution,


but felt that until sceptical concerns were dealt with, science


would always have to contend with Montaigne and his cronies,


standing on the sidelines and laughing at science’s pretenses to


knowledge. Descartes’ project, then, was to use the tools of the


sceptic to disprove the sceptical thesis by discovering certain


knowledge that could subsequently be used as the foundation of a


new science, in which knowledge about the external world was as


certain as knowledge about mathematics. It was also to hammer the


last nail into the coffin of scholasticism, but also, arguably,


to show that God still had a vital r_le to play in the discovery


of knowledge.


Meditation One describes Descartes’ method of doubt. By its


conclusion, Descartes has seemingly subjected all of his beliefs


to the strongest and most hyberbolic of doubts. He invokes the


nightmarish notion of an all-powerful, malign demon who could be


deceiving him in the realm of sensory experience, in his very


understanding of matter and even in the simplest cases of


mathematical or logical truths. The doubts may be obscure, but


this is the strength of the method – the weakness of criteria for


what makes a doubt reasonable means that almost anything can


count as a doubt, and therefore whatever withstands doubt must be


something epistemologically formidable.


In Meditation Two, Descartes hits upon the indubitable principle


he has been seeking. He exists, at least when he thinks he


exists. The cogito (Descartes’ proof of his own existence) has


been the source of a great deal of discussion ever since


Descartes first formulated it in the 1637 Discourse on Method,


and, I believe, a great deal of misinterpretation (quite possibly


as a result of Descartes’ repeated contradictions of his own


position in subsequent writings). Many commentators have fallen


prey to the tempting interpretation of the cogito as either


syllogism or enthymeme. This view holds that Descartes asserts


that he is thinking, that he believes it axiomatic that ‘whatever


thinks must exist’ and therefore that he logically concludes that


he exists. This view, it seems to me, is wrong. It should be


stated on no occasion, in the Meditations, does Descartes write


‘I am thinking, therefore I am’, nor anything directly


equivalent. Rather, he says:


“Doubtless, then, that I exist and, let him deceive me as


he may, he can never bring it about that I am nothing, so long as


I shall be conscious that I am something. So that it must, in


fine, be maintained, all things being maturely and carefully


considered, that this proposition I am, I exist, is necessarily


true each time it is expressed by me or conceived in my mind.”


(p. 80).


The point here is that it is impossible to doubt the truth of the


proposition ‘I exist’ when one utters it. It is an indubitable


proposition, and one that will necessarily be presupposed in


every attack of the sceptic. Descartes is not yet entitled to use


syllogisms as the possibility of the malign demon is still very


much alive. As an aside, Descartes himself denies that the cogito


is a syllogism, although it should be mentioned that in some of


the Replies to Objections he seems to assert that it is in fact


a syllogism. Finally, in the Regulae ad directionem ingenii,


Descartes denies the usefulness of syllogisms as a means to


knowledge.


I believe that, given Descartes’ project, it is fair to grant him


that the cogito deserves the status he bestows upon it. For can


there be anything more certain than something that is so forceful


and so powerful that every time it is presented to our mind we


are forced to assent to it?


What Descartes did here was to jiggle about the way philosophy


normally approaches the construction of knowledge structures. By


starting with self-knowledge, he elevates the subjective above


the objective and forces his epistemology to rest upon the


knowledge he has of his own self (and inadvertently sets the tone


for the next 300 years of philosophy). This leaves him with a


problem. He can know his own existence, that he is a thinking


thing and the contents of his consciousness, but how can any of


this ever lead to any knowledge of anything outside of himself?


The answer is that, by itself, it can’t. Descartes, in the third


Meditation, attempts to prove the existence of God, defined as a


being with all perfections. This proof is to be derived from his


idea of a God, defined as a being with all perfections. So far,


so good – Descartes examines the contents of his consciousness


and discovers within it this idea, and we can allow him this. At


this point, however, he introduces a whole series of scholastic


principles concerning different modes of causation and reality


without proper justification:


“For, without doubt, those [ideas considered as images, as


opposed to modes of consciousness] that represent substances are


something more, and contain in themselves, so to speak, more


objective reality, that is, participate by representation in


higher degrees of being or perfection than those that represent


only modes or accidents; and again the idea by which I conceive a


God has certainly in it more objective reality than those ideas


by which finite substances are represented.


Now it is manifest by the natural light that there must be


at least as much reality in the efficient and total cause as in


its effect; for whence can the effect draw its reality if not


from its cause? And how could the cause communicate to it this


reality unless it possessed it in itself?”


Whence do these principles draw their indubitability? Even if we


grant that it is contrary to natural reason that an effect can


have greater ‘reality’ than its cause, that the concepts of modes


and substances are coherent with Descartes’ method, let alone


possess the properties that he ascribes to them, then surely we


can still bring the malign demon into play? Is it not possible


that this all- powerful demon could bring it about that Descartes


has a notion of a being with all possible perfections that he


calls God? No, says Descartes, because the notion (representing


something perfect) would then have more objective reality than


the demon (as something evil and thus imperfect) has formal


reality, and ‘it is manifest by the natural light’ that this is


not possible. But why not? Maybe the demon has just made it seem


impossible, and it seems that Descartes has no answer to this.


Further problems remain. Cosmological arguments for God invoking


the notion of causation have always had to contend with the


problem of the cause of God. For if all events (or ideas) are


caused ultimately by God, then what about God Himself? Why should


He be exempt from this rule? The standard response to this is to


claim that God, being omnipotent, causes Himself. One of the


chief perfections that Descartes attributes to God is that of


’self-existence’, that is, that His existence depends on nothing


else but itself. But if we examine this idea, it seems a little


confused. If God is the efficient cause of God then we are forced


to ask how something that does not yet exist can cause anything.


If God is the formal cause of God, i.e. it is part of the


intrinsic nature of God that he exists – which seems more likely


- then it seems that we have merely a reformulation of the


ontological argument for God’s existence from Meditation 5.


It seems that Descartes may have anticipated the wealth of


criticism that the causal proof of God would inspire, and so,


after explaining how human error and a benevolent, non-deceiving


God are compatible in Meditation Four, he produced in Meditation


Five a version of the mediaeval ontological argument for God’s


existence. Unlike the causal argument, the ontological argument


doesn’t involve the covert import of any new principles. It


simply purports to show that, from an analysis of his own idea of


God, Descartes can show that He necessarily exists. The reasoning


goes like this:


I have ideas of things which have true and immutable natures. If


I perceive clearly and distinctly that a property belongs to an


idea’s true and immutable nature, then it does actually belong to


that nature. I perceive clearly and distinctly that God’s true


and mmutable nature is that of a being with all perfections.


Further, I perceive clearly and distinctly that existence is a


perfection and non-existence a non- perfection. Thus existence


belongs to God’s true and immutable nature. God exists.


One of the interesting things about this argument is that, at


first sight, it does not seem to depend in any way upon anything


that has been proved hitherto. It is an application of pure


logic, an analysis of what we mean when we say ‘God’ and a


inference from that analysis. Descartes explicitly says that an


idea’s true and immutable nature does not in any way depend upon


his thinking it, and thus upon his existence. Once he has


perceived clearly and distinctly that an idea’s true and


immutable nature consists in such-and-such, that is the case


whether or not he thinks it is, or even if he exists or not.


Descartes in fact recognises the primacy of the ontological


argument: “although all the conclusions of the preceding


Meditations were false, the existence of God would pass


with me for a truth at least as certain as I ever judged any


truth of mathematics to be.” If this is true, which it seems to


be, then this argument is only as trustworthy as the faculties


which enabled us to construct it, which are the same faculties


that enable us to know mathematical truths, and so it seems


worthwhile to ask how, under Descartes’ theory, we come to know


mathematical truths. Descartes claims we perceive them clearly


and distinctly. How do we know that what we perceive clearly and


distinctly is true? Because God, being perfect, is no deceiver,


and would not let it be the case that we could ever perceive


something clearly and distinctly without it being the case. It


seems then, that this proof of God, relying on the veracity of


clear and distinct ideas, relies on the certain knowledge that a


non-deceiving God exists. We have another proof of God, the


causal proof as described in Meditation three. But apart from the


patent futility of using one proof of p to construct another


proof of p, on examining the causal proof of God further, we find


that it, too, relies upon a methodology that can only be relied


upon if the divine guarantee is present, for if this guarantee is


not present, then, as I mentioned above, how can we be sure that


the all-powerful demon is not exercising his malignant influence?


This, of course, is the infamous Cartesian circle, first


identified by Arnauld in the Fourth Objections and discussed ever


since. Many philosophers have tried to get Descartes off the hook


in various ways, some by denying that there is a circle and some


by admitting the circularity but denying its significance. I will


here briefly evaluate a few of their arguments.


Some commentators have taken a passage from Descartes’ reply to


the Second set of Objections (Mersenne’s) to indicate that


Descartes is only actually interested in the psychological


significance of fundamental truths. The passage is as follows:


“If a conviction is so firm that that it is impossible for us


ever to have any reason for doubting what we are convinced of,


then there are no further questions for us to ask; we have


everything we could reasonably want.”


Under my interpretation, this is what it is about the cogito


that makes it so important for Descartes, so we cannot have any


argument with the principle expressed by him in the above


passage. But can it help break the circle? When we clearly and


distinctly perceive something, Descartes says, fairly I think,


that this perception compels our assent, that we cannot but


believe it. God’s r_le in the system, to these commentators, is


as a guarantor of our memory regarding clarity and distinctness.


In other words, once we have proved God’s existence, we can


happily know that any memory we have of a clear and distinct idea


regarding x is true i.e. that we really did have a clear and


distinct idea of x. But this does not seem satisfactory, as we


still do not have a divine guarantee for the reasoning that leads


us from the clear and distinct notions we originally have about


God to the proof of His existence. We can give assent to the


clear and distinct notions we have originally; in fact, we are


compelled to give this assent when the notions are presented to


our mind, but the logical steps we take from these ideas to the


final proof is still subject to the evil demon because God is not


yet proven. Furthermore, because these steps are needed, the


memory of the original clear and distinct ideas are themselves


subject to doubt because God is not yet proven. It seems that the


only way either of the proofs of God could be accepted would be


if we had an original clear and distinct perception of God


directly presented to our mind (qualitatively similar to the


cogito). But this in itself would make any future proofs


redundant. Interestingly, this sounds quite similar to a divine


revelation.


Harry Frankfurt, in his book ‘Demons, Dreamers and Madmen’, has


argued that what Descartes is actually looking for is a coherent,


indubitable set of beliefs about the universe. Whether they are


‘true’ or not is irrelevant. Perfect certainty is totally


compatible with absolute falsity. Our certainty may not coincide


precisely with ‘God’s’ truth, but should this matter?:


“Reason can give us certainty. It can serve to establish beliefs


in which there is no risk of betrayal. This certainty is all we


need and all we demand. Perhaps our certainties do not coincide


with God’s truth But this divine or absolute truth, since it is


outside the range of our faculties and cannot undermine our


certainties, need be of no concern to us.” (Frankfurt, p 184)


This is almost a Kantian approach to knowledge, where we as


humans only concern ourselves with the phenomena of objects as


they present themselves to us, not with the objects in


themselves. Can we ascribe this view to Descartes? It’s tempting,


given what we have said above regarding the prime importance of


indubitability, but it would seem that a God presenting ideas to


us in a form which doesn’t correspond to reality, and then giving


us a strong disposition to believe that they do correspond to


reality would be a deceiving God and contrary to Descartes’


notion of Him. Thus the belief set would not be coherent.


Perhaps, as we do not have clear and distinct ideas of the bodies


we perceive, and as the divine guarantee only extends as far as


clear and distinct ideas, we are being too hasty in judging that


reality is how it appears to be and if we stopped to meditate


further we would see that reality is actually like something


else. But aside from the fact that this seems unlikely,


Descartes never seemed to envisage the possibility.


So much for the Cartesian circle. Where does this leave the


ontological argument, which we had only just begun to discuss?


Aside from the methodological difficulties, there do seem to two


further problems with it. The first has been noted by almost


every student of Descartes over the years – that of the


description of existence as a property. Put briefly, this


objection states that existence is not a property like ‘red’ or


‘hairy’ or ‘three-sided’ that can be applied to a subject, and


thus it makes no sense to say that existence is part of


something’s essence. If we assert that x is y, we are already


asserting the existence of x as soon as we mention it, prior to


any application of a predicate. from the beginning. In


other words, to say ‘x exists’ is to utter a tautology and to say


that ‘x doesn’t exist’ is to contradict oneself. So how can


sentences of the form ‘x doesn’t exist’ make sense? one may well


ask. It is because these sentences are shorthand for ‘the idea I


have of x has no corresponding reality’ and it was to solve


problems like this that Bertrand Russell constructed his theory


of descriptions. To add existence to an idea doesn’t just make it


an idea with a new property, it changes it from an idea into an


existent entity.


Finally, if Descartes is right, there seems no reason why we


cannot construct any other idea whose essence includes


existence. For instance, if I conjure up the idea of an existent


purple building that resembles the Taj Mahal’, then it is the


true and immutable nature of this idea that it is a building,


that this building resembles the Taj Mahal, that the building is


purple, and that it exists. But no such building does exist, as


far as I am aware, and if it did exist, its existence would not


be necessary, but contingent. This in itself is enough, I think,


to show that the ontological argument is false.


Once we have destroyed Descartes’ proofs of the existence of God,


the edifice of knowledge necessarily comes tumbling down with


them, as we find that almost everything Descartes believes in is


dependent on God’s nature as a non-deceiver:


“I remark that the certitude of all other truths is so absolutely


dependent on it, that without this knowledge it is impossible


ever to know anything perfectly.” (p.115)


The only possible exceptions are those assent-compelling beliefs


such as the cogito. Even these, however, are doubtful when we


are not thinking about them, and the above passage does give


weight to Edwin Curley’s argument that:


“Descartes would hold that the proposition “I exist” is fully


certain only if the rest of the argument of the Meditations goes


through. We must buy all or nothing.”


This is not the end of the story, though. As far as Descartes is


concerned, by the end of Meditation Five, he has produced two


powerful proofs of God, has a clear and distinct notion of his


own self, has a criterion for truth, knows how to avoid error and


is beginning to form ideas regarding our knowledge of corporeal


bodies.. And so it remains only to explain why we are fully


justified in believing in corporeal bodies, and also to draw the


ideas of Meditation Two regarding self-knowledge to their full


conclusion.


Regarding the nature of corporeal bodies and our knowledge of


them, it seems to me that, given his premises, the conclusions


Descartes draws in Meditation Six are generally the correct ones.


He again invokes the causal to argue that the ideas of bodies we


have within our minds must be caused by something with at least


as much formal reality as the ideas have objective reality. We


could theoretically be producing these ideas, but Descartes


dismisses this possibility for two reasons – firstly, that the


idea of corporeality does not presuppose thought and secondly


that our will seems to have no effect on what we perceive or


don’t perceive. (This second argument seems to me to ignore


dreaming, in which what we perceive derives from us but is


independent of our will). The ideas, then, could come from God,


or from another being superior to us but inferior to God. But


this, too, is impossible, argues Descartes, as if it were the


case that God produces the ideas of bodies in us, then the very


strong inclination we have towards believing that the idea-


producing bodies resemble the ideas we have would be false and


thus God would be allowing us to be deceived which is not


permissible. The same would apply if any other being were


producing these ideas. Thus, concludes Descartes, it is most


likely that our ideas of corporeal bodies are actually caused by


bodies resembling those ideas. We cannot be certain, however, as


we cannot claim to have clear and distinct notions of everything


we perceive. We can, however, claim certainty with regard to


those properties of bodies which we do know with clarity and


distinction; namely, size, figure (shape), position, motion,


substance, duration and number (not all of these assertions are


justified). Obviously we cannot claim that we know these


properties for specific bodies with clarity and distinction, for


to do so would leave open the uestion of why it is that


astronomy and the senses attribute different sizes to stars. What


Descartes means is that we can be sure that these primary


qualities exist in bodies in the same way that they do in our


ideas of bodies. This cannot be claimed for qualities such as


heat, colour, taste and smell, of which our ideas are so confused


and vague that we must always reserve judgement. (This conclusion


is actually quite similar to the one John Locke drew fifty years


later in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding.)


I think we can grant this reasoning, with the caveat regarding


dreaming that I noted above, and of course the other unproved


reasonings that Descartes exhumes here, such as the causal


principle. Furthermore, it seems to be further proof that


Descartes does believe we can get to know objects in themselves


to a certain extent.


Finally, I turn to Descartes’ argument for the distinction of


mind and body. Descartes believes he has shown the mind to be


better known than the body in Meditation Two. In Meditation Six


he goes on to claim that, as he knows his mind and knows clearly


and distinctly that its essence consists purely of thought, and


that bodies’ essences consist purely of extension, that he can


conceive of his mind and body as existing separately. By the


power of God, anything that can be clearly and distinctly


conceived of as existing separately from something else can be


created as existing separately. At this point, Descartes makes


the apparent logical leap to claiming that the mind and body have


been created separately, without justification. Most commentators


agree that this is not justified, and further, that just because


I can conceive of my mind existing independently of my body it


does not necessarily follow that it does so. In defence of


Descartes, Saul Kripke has suggested that Descartes may have


anticipated a modern strand of modal logic that holds that if


x=y, then L (x=y). In other words, if x is identical to y then it


is necessarily identical to it. From this it follows that if it


is logically possible that x and y have different properties then


they are distinct. In this instance, that means that because I


can clearly and distinctly conceive of my mind and body as


existing separately, then they are distinct. The argument, like


much modern work on identity, is too technical and involved to


explore here in much depth. But suffice to say that we can


clearly and distinctly conceive of Dr Jekyll and Mr. Hyde as


being distinct and yet they are identical, necessarily so under


Kripke’s theory. It is doubtful that Kripke can come to


Descartes’ aid here and Descartes needs further argument to prove


that the mind and the body are distinct.


And so we finish our discussion of Descartes’ attempts to


extricate himself from the sceptical doubts he has set up for


himself. As mentioned previously, the ultimate conclusion to draw


regarding the success of the enterprise that Descartes set for


himself must be that he failed. When the whole epistemological


structure is so heavily dependent on one piece of knowledge – in


this case the knowledge that God exists – then a denial of that


knowledge destroys the whole structure. All that we can really


grant Descartes – and this is certainly contentious – is that he


can rightly claim that when a clear and distinct idea presents


itself to his mind, he cannot but give his assent to this idea,


and furthermore, that while this assent is being granted, the


clear and distinct idea can be justly used as a foundation for


knowledge. The most this gets us – and this is not a little – is


the knowledge of our own existence each time we assert it. But


Descartes’ project should not be judged by us as a failure – the


fact that he addressed topics of great and lasting interest, and


provided us with a method we can both understand and utilise


fruitfully, speaks for itself.


Bibliography


1. Descartes, Ren_ A Discourse on Method, Meditations and


Principles of Philosophy trans. John Veitch. The Everyman’s


Library, 1995.


Descartes, Ren_ The Philosophical Writings of Descartes volume I


and II ed. and trans. John Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and D.


Murdoch. Cambridge, 1985.


Frankfurt, Harry Demons, Dreamers and Madmen. Bobbs-Merrill,


1970.


Curley, Edwin Descartes Against the Skeptics. Oxford, 1978.


Vesey, Godfrey Descartes: Father of Modern Philosophy. Open


University Press, 1971.


Sorrell, Tom Descartes: Reason and Experience. Open University


Press, 1982.


The Oxford Companion to Philosophy ed. Ted Honderich. Oxford


University Press, 1985.


Cottingham, John Descartes. Oxford, 1986. Williams, Bernard


Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. Harmondsworth, 1978.


Russell, Bertrand The History of Western Philosophy. George Allen


and Unwin, 1961. 11. Kripke, Saul Naming and Necessity. Oxford


1980.>


Descartes


How does Descartes try to extricate himself from the sceptical


doubts that he has raised? Does he succeed?


by Tom Nuttall


[All page references and quotations from the Meditations are


taken from the 1995 Everyman edition]


In the Meditations, Descartes embarks upon what Bernard Williams


has called the project of ‘Pure Enquiry’ to discover certain,


indubitable foundations for knowledge. By subjecting everything


to doubt Descartes hoped to discover whatever was immune to it.


In order to best understand how and why Descartes builds his


epistemological system up from his foundations in the way that he


does, it is helpful to gain an understanding of the intellectual


background of the 17th century that provided the motivation for


his work.


We can discern three distinct influences on Descartes, three


conflicting world-views that fought for prominence in his day.


The first was what remained of the mediaeval scholastic


philosophy, largely based on Aristotelian science and Christian


theology. Descartes had been taught according to this outlook


during his time at the Jesuit college La Flech_ and it had an


important influence on his work, as we shall see later. The


second was the scepticism that had made a sudden impact on the


intellectual world, mainly as a reaction to the scholastic


outlook. This scepticism was strongly influenced by the work of


the Pyrrhonians as handed down from antiquity by Sextus


Empiricus, which claimed that, as there is never a reason to


believe p that is better than a reason not to believe p, we


should forget about trying to discover the nature of reality and


live by appearance alone. This attitude was best exemplified in


the work of Michel de Montaigne, who mockingly dismissed the


attempts of theologians and scientists to understand the nature


of God and the universe respectively. Descartes felt the force of


sceptical arguments and, while not being sceptically disposed


himself, came to believe that scepticism towards knowledge was


the best way to discover what is certain: by applying sceptical


doubt to all our beliefs, we can discover which of them are


indubitable, and thus form an adequate foundation for knowledge.


The third world-view resulted largely from the work of the new


scientists; Galileo, Copernicus, Bacon et al. Science had finally


begun to assert itself and shake off its dated Aristotelian


prejudices. Coherent theories about the world and its place in


the universe were being constructed and many of those who were


aware of this work became very optimistic about the influence it


could have. Descartes was a child of the scientific revolution,


but felt that until sceptical concerns were dealt with, science


would always have to contend with Montaigne and his cronies,


standing on the sidelines and laughing at science’s pretenses to


knowledge. Descartes’ project, then, was to use the tools of the


sceptic to disprove the sceptical thesis by discovering certain


knowledge that could subsequently be used as the foundation of a


new science, in which knowledge about the external world was as


certain as knowledge about mathematics. It was also to hammer the


last nail into the coffin of scholasticism, but also, arguably,


to show that God still had a vital r_le to play in the discovery


of knowledge.


Meditation One describes Descartes’ method of doubt. By its


conclusion, Descartes has seemingly subjected all of his beliefs


to the strongest and most hyberbolic of doubts. He invokes the


nightmarish notion of an all-powerful, malign demon who could be


deceiving him in the realm of sensory experience, in his very


understanding of matter and even in the simplest cases of


mathematical or logical truths. The doubts may be obscure, but


this is the strength of the method – the weakness of criteria for


what makes a doubt reasonable means that almost anything can


count as a doubt, and therefore whatever withstands doubt must be


something epistemologically formidable.


In Meditation Two, Descartes hits upon the indubitable principle


he has been seeking. He exists, at least when he thinks he


exists. The cog

ito (Descartes’ proof of his own existence) has


been the source of a great deal of discussion ever since


Descartes first formulated it in the 1637 Discourse on Method,


and, I believe, a great deal of misinterpretation (quite possibly


as a result of Descartes’ repeated contradictions of his own


position in subsequent writings). Many commentators have fallen


prey to the tempting interpretation of the cogito as either


syllogism or enthymeme. This view holds that Descartes asserts


that he is thinking, that he believes it axiomatic that ‘whatever


thinks must exist’ and therefore that he logically concludes that


he exists. This view, it seems to me, is wrong. It should be


stated on no occasion, in the Meditations, does Descartes write


‘I am thinking, therefore I am’, nor anything directly


equivalent. Rather, he says:


“Doubtless, then, that I exist and, let him deceive me as


he may, he can never bring it about that I am nothing, so long as


I shall be conscious that I am something. So that it must, in


fine, be maintained, all things being maturely and carefully


considered, that this proposition I am, I exist, is necessarily


true each time it is expressed by me or conceived in my mind.”


(p. 80).


The point here is that it is impossible to doubt the truth of the


proposition ‘I exist’ when one utters it. It is an indubitable


proposition, and one that will necessarily be presupposed in


every attack of the sceptic. Descartes is not yet entitled to use


syllogisms as the possibility of the malign demon is still very


much alive. As an aside, Descartes himself denies that the cogito


is a syllogism, although it should be mentioned that in some of


the Replies to Objections he seems to assert that it is in fact


a syllogism. Finally, in the Regulae ad directionem ingenii,


Descartes denies the usefulness of syllogisms as a means to


knowledge.


I believe that, given Descartes’ project, it is fair to grant him


that the cogito deserves the status he bestows upon it. For can


there be anything more certain than something that is so forceful


and so powerful that every time it is presented to our mind we


are forced to assent to it?


What Descartes did here was to jiggle about the way philosophy


normally approaches the construction of knowledge structures. By


starting with self-knowledge, he elevates the subjective above


the objective and forces his epistemology to rest upon the


knowledge he has of his own self (and inadvertently sets the tone


for the next 300 years of philosophy). This leaves him with a


problem. He can know his own existence, that he is a thinking


thing and the contents of his consciousness, but how can any of


this ever lead to any knowledge of anything outside of himself?


The answer is that, by itself, it can’t. Descartes, in the third


Meditation, attempts to prove the existence of God, defined as a


being with all perfections. This proof is to be derived from his


idea of a God, defined as a being with all perfections. So far,


so good – Descartes examines the contents of his consciousness


and discovers within it this idea, and we can allow him this. At


this point, however, he introduces a whole series of scholastic


principles concerning different modes of causation and reality


without proper justification:


“For, without doubt, those [ideas considered as images, as


opposed to modes of consciousness] that represent substances are


something more, and contain in themselves, so to speak, more


objective reality, that is, participate by representation in


higher degrees of being or perfection than those that represent


only modes or accidents; and again the idea by which I conceive a


God has certainly in it more objective reality than those ideas


by which finite substances are represented.


Now it is manifest by the natural light that there must be


at least as much reality in the efficient and total cause as in


its effect; for whence can the effect draw its reality if not


from its cause? And how could the cause communicate to it this


reality unless it possessed it in itself?”


Whence do these principles draw their indubitability? Even if we


grant that it is contrary to natural reason that an effect can


have greater ‘reality’ than its cause, that the concepts of modes


and substances are coherent with Descartes’ method, let alone


possess the properties that he ascribes to them, then surely we


can still bring the malign demon into play? Is it not possible


that this all- powerful demon could bring it about that Descartes


has a notion of a being with all possible perfections that he


calls God? No, says Descartes, because the notion (representing


something perfect) would then have more objective reality than


the demon (as something evil and thus imperfect) has formal


reality, and ‘it is manifest by the natural light’ that this is


not possible. But why not? Maybe the demon has just made it seem


impossible, and it seems that Descartes has no answer to this.


Further problems remain. Cosmological arguments for God invoking


the notion of causation have always had to contend with the


problem of the cause of God. For if all events (or ideas) are


caused ultimately by God, then what about God Himself? Why should


He be exempt from this rule? The standard response to this is to


claim that God, being omnipotent, causes Himself. One of the


chief perfections that Descartes attributes to God is that of


’self-existence’, that is, that His existence depends on nothing


else but itself. But if we examine this idea, it seems a little


confused. If God is the efficient cause of God then we are forced


to ask how something that does not yet exist can cause anything.


If God is the formal cause of God, i.e. it is part of the


intrinsic nature of God that he exists – which seems more likely


- then it seems that we have merely a reformulation of the


ontological argument for God’s existence from Meditation 5.


It seems that Descartes may have anticipated the wealth of


criticism that the causal proof of God would inspire, and so,


after explaining how human error and a benevolent, non-deceiving


God are compatible in Meditation Four, he produced in Meditation


Five a version of the mediaeval ontological argument for God’s


existence. Unlike the causal argument, the ontological argument


doesn’t involve the covert import of any new principles. It


simply purports to show that, from an analysis of his own idea of


God, Descartes can show that He necessarily exists. The reasoning


goes like this:


I have ideas of things which have true and immutable natures. If


I perceive clearly and distinctly that a property belongs to an


idea’s true and immutable nature, then it does actually belong to


that nature. I perceive clearly and distinctly that God’s true


and mmutable nature is that of a being with all perfections.


Further, I perceive clearly and distinctly that existence is a


perfection and non-existence a non- perfection. Thus existence


belongs to God’s true and immutable nature. God exists.


One of the interesting things about this argument is that, at


first sight, it does not seem to depend in any way upon anything


that has been proved hitherto. It is an application of pure


logic, an analysis of what we mean when we say ‘God’ and a


inference from that analysis. Descartes explicitly says that an


idea’s true and immutable nature does not in any way depend upon


his thinking it, and thus upon his existence. Once he has


perceived clearly and distinctly that an idea’s true and


immutable nature consists in such-and-such, that is the case


whether or not he thinks it is, or even if he exists or not.


Descartes in fact recognises the primacy of the ontological


argument: “although all the conclusions of the preceding


Meditations were false, the existence of God would pass


with me for a truth at least as certain as I ever judged any


truth of mathematics to be.” If this is true, which it seems to


be, then this argument is only as trustworthy as the faculties


which enabled us to construct it, which are the same faculties


that enable us to know mathematical truths, and so it seems


worthwhile to ask how, under Descartes’ theory, we come to know


mathematical truths. Descartes claims we perceive them clearly


and distinctly. How do we know that what we perceive clearly and


distinctly is true? Because God, being perfect, is no deceiver,


and would not let it be the case that we could ever perceive


something clearly and distinctly without it being the case. It


seems then, that this proof of God, relying on the veracity of


clear and distinct ideas, relies on the certain knowledge that a


non-deceiving God exists. We have another proof of God, the


causal proof as described in Meditation three. But apart from the


patent futility of using one proof of p to construct another


proof of p, on examining the causal proof of God further, we find


that it, too, relies upon a methodology that can only be relied


upon if the divine guarantee is present, for if this guarantee is


not present, then, as I mentioned above, how can we be sure that


the all-powerful demon is not exercising his malignant influence?


This, of course, is the infamous Cartesian circle, first


identified by Arnauld in the Fourth Objections and discussed ever


since. Many philosophers have tried to get Descartes off the hook


in various ways, some by denying that there is a circle and some


by admitting the circularity but denying its significance. I will


here briefly evaluate a few of their arguments.


Some commentators have taken a passage from Descartes’ reply to


the Second set of Objections (Mersenne’s) to indicate that


Descartes is only actually interested in the psychological


significance of fundamental truths. The passage is as follows:


“If a conviction is so firm that that it is impossible for us


ever to have any reason for doubting what we are convinced of,


then there are no further questions for us to ask; we have


everything we could reasonably want.”


Under my interpretation, this is what it is about the cogito


that makes it so important for Descartes, so we cannot have any


argument with the principle expressed by him in the above


passage. But can it help break the circle? When we clearly and


distinctly perceive something, Descartes says, fairly I think,


that this perception compels our assent, that we cannot but


believe it. God’s r_le in the system, to these commentators, is


as a guarantor of our memory regarding clarity and distinctness.


In other words, once we have proved God’s existence, we can


happily know that any memory we have of a clear and distinct idea


regarding x is true i.e. that we really did have a clear and


distinct idea of x. But this does not seem satisfactory, as we


still do not have a divine guarantee for the reasoning that leads


us from the clear and distinct notions we originally have about


God to the proof of His existence. We can give assent to the


clear and distinct notions we have originally; in fact, we are


compelled to give this assent when the notions are presented to


our mind, but the logical steps we take from these ideas to the


final proof is still subject to the evil demon because God is not


yet proven. Furthermore, because these steps are needed, the


memory of the original clear and distinct ideas are themselves


subject to doubt because God is not yet proven. It seems that the


only way either of the proofs of God could be accepted would be


if we had an original clear and distinct perception of God


directly presented to our mind (qualitatively similar to the


cogito). But this in itself would make any future proofs


redundant. Interestingly, this sounds quite similar to a divine


revelation.


Harry Frankfurt, in his book ‘Demons, Dreamers and Madmen’, has


argued that what Descartes is actually looking for is a coherent,


indubitable set of beliefs about the universe. Whether they are


‘true’ or not is irrelevant. Perfect certainty is totally


compatible with absolute falsity. Our certainty may not coincide


precisely with ‘God’s’ truth, but should this matter?:


“Reason can give us certainty. It can serve to establish beliefs


in which there is no risk of betrayal. This certainty is all we


need and all we demand. Perhaps our certainties do not coincide


with God’s truth But this divine or absolute truth, since it is


outside the range of our faculties and cannot undermine our


certainties, need be of no concern to us.” (Frankfurt, p 184)


This is almost a Kantian approach to knowledge, where we as


humans only concern ourselves with the phenomena of objects as


they present themselves to us, not with the objects in


themselves. Can we ascribe this view to Descartes? It’s tempting,


given what we have said above regarding the prime importance of


indubitability, but it would seem that a God presenting ideas to


us in a form which doesn’t correspond to reality, and then giving


us a strong disposition to believe that they do correspond to


reality would be a deceiving God and contrary to Descartes’


notion of Him. Thus the belief set would not be coherent.


Perhaps, as we do not have clear and distinct ideas of the bodies


we perceive, and as the divine guarantee only extends as far as


clear and distinct ideas, we are being too hasty in judging that


reality is how it appears to be and if we stopped to meditate


further we would see that reality is actually like something


else. But aside from the fact that this seems unlikely,


Descartes never seemed to envisage the possibility.


So much for the Cartesian circle. Where does this leave the


ontological argument, which we had only just begun to discuss?


Aside from the methodological difficulties, there do seem to two


further problems with it. The first has been noted by almost


every student of Descartes over the years – that of the


description of existence as a property. Put briefly, this


objection states that existence is not a property like ‘red’ or


‘hairy’ or ‘three-sided’ that can be applied to a subject, and


thus it makes no sense to say that existence is part of


something’s essence. If we assert that x is y, we are already


asserting the existence of x as soon as we mention it, prior to


any application of a predicate. from the beginning. In


other words, to say ‘x exists’ is to utter a tautology and to say


that ‘x doesn’t exist’ is to contradict oneself. So how can


sentences of the form ‘x doesn’t exist’ make sense? one may well


ask. It is because these sentences are shorthand for ‘the idea I


have of x has no corresponding reality’ and it was to solve


problems like this that Bertrand Russell constructed his theory


of descriptions. To add existence to an idea doesn’t just make it


an idea with a new property, it changes it from an idea into an


existent entity.


Finally, if Descartes is right, there seems no reason why we


cannot construct any other idea whose essence includes


existence. For instance, if I conjure up the idea of an existent


purple building that resembles the Taj Mahal’, then it is the


true and immutable nature of this idea that it is a building,


that this building resembles the Taj Mahal, that the building is


purple, and that it exists. But no such building does exist, as


far as I am aware, and if it did exist, its existence would not


be necessary, but contingent. This in itself is enough, I think,


to show that the ontological argument is false.


Once we have destroyed Descartes’ proofs of the existence of God,


the edifice of knowledge necessarily comes tumbling down with


them, as we find that almost everything Descartes believes in is


dependent on God’s nature as a non-deceiver:


“I remark that the certitude of all other truths is so absolutely


dependent on it, that without this knowledge it is impossible


ever to know anything perfectly.” (p.115)


The only possible exceptions are those assent-compelling beliefs


such as the cogito. Even these, however, are doubtful when we


are not thinking about them, and the above passage does give


weight to Edwin Curley’s argument that:


“Descartes would hold that the proposition “I exist” is fully


certain only if the rest of the argument of the Meditations goes


through. We must buy all or nothing.”


This is not the end of the story, though. As far as Descartes is


concerned, by the end of Meditation Five, he has produced two


powerful proofs of God, has a clear and distinct notion of his


own self, has a criterion for truth, knows how to avoid error and


is beginning to form ideas regarding our knowledge of corporeal


bodies.. And so it remains only to explain why we are fully


justified in believing in corporeal bodies, and also to draw the


ideas of Meditation Two regarding self-knowledge to their full


conclusion.


Regarding the nature of corporeal bodies and our knowledge of


them, it seems to me that, given his premises, the conclusions


Descartes draws in Meditation Six are generally the correct ones.


He again invokes the causal to argue that the ideas of bodies we


have within our minds must be caused by something with at least


as much formal reality as the ideas have objective reality. We


could theoretically be producing these ideas, but Descartes


dismisses this possibility for two reasons – firstly, that the


idea of corporeality does not presuppose thought and secondly


that our will seems to have no effect on what we perceive or


don’t perceive. (This second argument seems to me to ignore


dreaming, in which what we perceive derives from us but is


independent of our will). The ideas, then, could come from God,


or from another being superior to us but inferior to God. But


this, too, is impossible, argues Descartes, as if it were the


case that God produces the ideas of bodies in us, then the very


strong inclination we have towards believing that the idea-


producing bodies resemble the ideas we have would be false and


thus God would be allowing us to be deceived which is not


permissible. The same would apply if any other being were


producing these ideas. Thus, concludes Descartes, it is most


likely that our ideas of corporeal bodies are actually caused by


bodies resembling those ideas. We cannot be certain, however, as


we cannot claim to have clear and distinct notions of everything


we perceive. We can, however, claim certainty with regard to


those properties of bodies which we do know with clarity and


distinction; namely, size, figure (shape), position, motion,


substance, duration and number (not all of these assertions are


justified). Obviously we cannot claim that we know these


properties for specific bodies with clarity and distinction, for


to do so would leave open the uestion of why it is that


astronomy and the senses attribute different sizes to stars. What


Descartes means is that we can be sure that these primary


qualities exist in bodies in the same way that they do in our


ideas of bodies. This cannot be claimed for qualities such as


heat, colour, taste and smell, of which our ideas are so confused


and vague that we must always reserve judgement. (This conclusion


is actually quite similar to the one John Locke drew fifty years


later in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding.)


I think we can grant this reasoning, with the caveat regarding


dreaming that I noted above, and of course the other unproved


reasonings that Descartes exhumes here, such as the causal


principle. Furthermore, it seems to be further proof that


Descartes does believe we can get to know objects in themselves


to a certain extent.


Finally, I turn to Descartes’ argument for the distinction of


mind and body. Descartes believes he has shown the mind to be


better known than the body in Meditation Two. In Meditation Six


he goes on to claim that, as he knows his mind and knows clearly


and distinctly that its essence consists purely of thought, and


that bodies’ essences consist purely of extension, that he can


conceive of his mind and body as existing separately. By the


power of God, anything that can be clearly and distinctly


conceived of as existing separately from something else can be


created as existing separately. At this point, Descartes makes


the apparent logical leap to claiming that the mind and body have


been created separately, without justification. Most commentators


agree that this is not justified, and further, that just because


I can conceive of my mind existing independently of my body it


does not necessarily follow that it does so. In defence of


Descartes, Saul Kripke has suggested that Descartes may have


anticipated a modern strand of modal logic that holds that if


x=y, then L (x=y). In other words, if x is identical to y then it


is necessarily identical to it. From this it follows that if it


is logically possible that x and y have different properties then


they are distinct. In this instance, that means that because I


can clearly and distinctly conceive of my mind and body as


existing separately, then they are distinct. The argument, like


much modern work on identity, is too technical and involved to


explore here in much depth. But suffice to say that we can


clearly and distinctly conceive of Dr Jekyll and Mr. Hyde as


being distinct and yet they are identical, necessarily so under


Kripke’s theory. It is doubtful that Kripke can come to


Descartes’ aid here and Descartes needs further argument to prove


that the mind and the body are distinct.


And so we finish our discussion of Descartes’ attempts to


extricate himself from the sceptical doubts he has set up for


himself. As mentioned previously, the ultimate conclusion to draw


regarding the success of the enterprise that Descartes set for


himself must be that he failed. When the whole epistemological


structure is so heavily dependent on one piece of knowledge – in


this case the knowledge that God exists – then a denial of that


knowledge destroys the whole structure. All that we can really


grant Descartes – and this is certainly contentious – is that he


can rightly claim that when a clear and distinct idea presents


itself to his mind, he cannot but give his assent to this idea,


and furthermore, that while this assent is being granted, the


clear and distinct idea can be justly used as a foundation for


knowledge. The most this gets us – and this is not a little – is


the knowledge of our own existence each time we assert it. But


Descartes’ project should not be judged by us as a failure – the


fact that he addressed topics of great and lasting interest, and


provided us with a method we can both understand and utilise


fruitfully, speaks for itself.


Bibliography


1. Descartes, Ren_ A Discourse on Method, Meditations and


Principles of Philosophy trans. John Veitch. The Everyman’s


Library, 1995.


Descartes, Ren_ The Philosophical Writings of Descartes volume I


and II ed. and trans. John Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and D.


Murdoch. Cambridge, 1985.


Frankfurt, Harry Demons, Dreamers and Madmen. Bobbs-Merrill,


1970.


Curley, Edwin Descartes Against the Skeptics. Oxford, 1978.


Vesey, Godfrey Descartes: Father of Modern Philosophy. Open


University Press, 1971.


Sorrell, Tom Descartes: Reason and Experience. Open University


Press, 1982.


The Oxford Companion to Philosophy ed. Ted Honderich. Oxford


University Press, 1985.


Cottingham, John Descartes. Oxford, 1986. Williams, Bernard


Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. Harmondsworth, 1978.


Russell, Bertrand The History of Western Philosophy. George Allen


and Unwin, 1961. 11. Kripke, Saul Naming and Necessity. Oxford


1980.>


Descartes


How does Descartes try to extricate himself from the sceptical


doubts that he has raised? Does he succeed?


by Tom Nuttall


[All page references and quotations from the Meditations are


taken from the 1995 Everyman edition]


In the Meditations, Descartes embarks upon what Bernard Williams


has called the project of ‘Pure Enquiry’ to discover certain,


indubitable foundations for knowledge. By subjecting everything


to doubt Descartes hoped to discover whatever was immune to it.


In order to best understand how and why Descartes builds his


epistemological system up from his foundations in the way that he


does, it is helpful to gain an understanding of the intellectual


background of the 17th century that provided the motivation for


his work.


We can discern three distinct influences on Descartes, three


conflicting world-views that fought for prominence in his day.


The first was what remained of the mediaeval scholastic


philosophy, largely based on Aristotelian science and Christian


theology. Descartes had been taught according to this outlook


during his time at the Jesuit college La Flech_ and it had an


important influence on his work, as we shall see later. The


second was the scepticism that had made a sudden impact on the


intellectual world, mainly as a reaction to the scholastic


outlook. This scepticism was strongly influenced by the work of


the Pyrrhonians as handed down from antiquity by Sextus


Empiricus, which claimed that, as there is never a reason to


believe p that is better than a reason not to believe p, we


should forget about trying to discover the nature of reality and


live by appearance alone. This attitude was best exemplified in


the work of Michel de Montaigne, who mockingly dismissed the


attempts of theologians and scientists to understand the nature


of God and the universe respectively. Descartes felt the force of


sceptical arguments and, while not being sceptically disposed


himself, came to believe that scepticism towards knowledge was


the best way to discover what is certain: by applying sceptical


doubt to all our beliefs, we can discover which of them are


indubitable, and thus form an adequate foundation for knowledge.


The third world-view resulted largely from the work of the new


scientists; Galileo, Copernicus, Bacon et al. Science had finally


begun to assert itself and shake off its dated Aristotelian


prejudices. Coherent theories about the world and its place in


the universe were being constructed and many of those who were


aware of this work became very optimistic about the influence it


could have. Descartes was a child of the scientific revolution,


but felt that until sceptical concerns were dealt with, science


would always have to contend with Montaigne and his cronies,


standing on the sidelines and laughing at science’s pretenses to


knowledge. Descartes’ project, then, was to use the tools of the


sceptic to disprove the sceptical thesis by discovering certain


knowledge that could subsequently be used as the foundation of a


new science, in which knowledge about the external world was as


certain as knowledge about mathematics. It was also to hammer the


last nail into the coffin of scholasticism, but also, arguably,


to show that God still had a vital r_le to play in the discovery


of knowledge.


Meditation One describes Descartes’ method of doubt. By its


conclusion, Descartes has seemingly subjected all of his beliefs


to the strongest and most hyberbolic of doubts. He invokes the


nightmarish notion of an all-powerful, malign demon who could be


deceiving him in the realm of sensory experience, in his very


understanding of matter and even in the simplest cases of


mathematical or logical truths. The doubts may be obscure, but


this is the strength of the method – the weakness of criteria for


what makes a doubt reasonable means that almost anything can


count as a doubt, and therefore whatever withstands doubt must be


something epistemologically formidable.


In Meditation Two, Descartes hits upon the indubitable principle


he has been seeking. He exists, at least when he thinks he


exists. The cogito (Descartes’ proof of his own existence) has


been the source of a great deal of discussion ever since


Descartes first formulated it in the 1637 Discourse on Method,


and, I believe, a great deal of misinterpretation (quite possibly


as a result of Descartes’ repeated contradictions of his own


position in subsequent writings). Many commentators have fallen


prey to the tempting interpretation of the cogito as either


syllogism or enthymeme. This view holds that Descartes asserts


that he is thinking, that he believes it axiomatic that ‘whatever


thinks must exist’ and therefore that he logically concludes that


he exists. This view, it seems to me, is wrong. It should be


stated on no occasion, in the Meditations, does Descartes write


‘I am thinking, therefore I am’, nor anything directly


equivalent. Rather, he says:


“Doubtless, then, that I exist and, let him deceive me as


he may, he can never bring it about that I am nothing, so long as


I shall be conscious that I am something. So that it must, in


fine, be maintained, all things being maturely and carefully


considered, that this proposition I am, I exist, is necessarily


true each time it is expressed by me or conceived in my mind.”


(p. 80).


The point here is that it is impossible to doubt the truth of the


proposition ‘I exist’ when one utters it. It is an indubitable


proposition, and one that will necessarily be presupposed in


every attack of the sceptic. Descartes is not yet entitled to use


syllogisms as the possibility of the malign demon is still very


much alive. As an aside, Descartes himself denies that the cogito


is a syllogism, although it should be mentioned that in some of


the Replies to Objections he seems to assert that it is in fact


a syllogism. Finally, in the Regulae ad directionem ingenii,


Descartes denies the usefulness of syllogisms as a means to


knowledge.


I believe that, given Descartes’ project, it is fair to grant him


that the cogito deserves the status he bestows upon it. For can


there be anything more certain than something that is so forceful


and so powerful that every time it is presented to our mind we


are forced to assent to it?


What Descartes did here was to jiggle about the way philosophy


normally approaches the construction of knowledge structures. By


starting with self-knowledge, he elevates the subjective above


the objective and forces his epistemology to rest upon the


knowledge he has of his own self (and inadvertently sets the tone


for the next 300 years of philosophy). This leaves him with a


problem. He can know his own existence, that he is a thinking


thing and the contents of his consciousness, but how can any of


this ever lead to any knowledge of anything outside of himself?


The answer is that, by itself, it can’t. Descartes, in the third


Meditation, attempts to prove the existence of God, defined as a


being with all perfections. This proof is to be derived from his


idea of a God, defined as a being with all perfections. So far,


so good – Descartes examines the contents of his consciousness


and discovers within it this idea, and we can allow him this. At


this point, however, he introduces a whole series of scholastic


principles concerning different modes of causation and reality


without proper justification:


“For, without doubt, those [ideas considered as images, as


opposed to modes of consciousness] that represent substances are


something more, and contain in themselves, so to speak, more


objective reality, that is, participate by representation in


higher degrees of being or perfection than those that represent


only modes or accidents; and again the idea by which I conceive a


God has certainly in it more objective reality than those ideas


by which finite substances are represented.


Now it is manifest by the natural light that there must be


at least as much reality in the efficient and total cause as in


its effect; for whence can the effect draw its reality if not


from its cause? And how could the cause communicate to it this


reality unless it possessed it in itself?”


Whence do these principles draw their indubitability? Even if we


grant that it is contrary to natural rea

Сохранить в соц. сетях:
Обсуждение:
comments powered by Disqus

Название реферата: Descarte 2 Essay Research Paper DescartesHow does

Слов:11763
Символов:77771
Размер:151.90 Кб.