РефератыИностранный языкOtOther Minds Essay Research Paper The problem

Other Minds Essay Research Paper The problem

Other Minds Essay, Research Paper


The problem of Other Minds is a true


philosophical enigma. It is apt to strike children with no philosophical


education whatsoever, yet remains intractable to many academics. Broadly


speaking, the problem can be divided into three questions. Firstly, how do


I come to believe that there are minds in the world other than my own?


Secondly, how can I justify my belief that there are minds in the world


other than my own? Thirdly, what can I state about the mental states of


minds other than my own?. The question we are dealing with here falls


largely into the third category, although of course issues relating to the


other two will also be involved.


Firstly, it is imperative to assert that, in looking for ?knowledge?, we


are not aiming for logical certainties – we are not aiming to show that


any propositions about other minds can be demonstrated with absolute


certainty equivalent to that of mathematical truths. Philosophy ever


since Descartes has tended to be defined by scepticism: either it aims to


produce sceptical theories or it aims to refute them. And sceptics tend


towards extremity in their doubts. It must be stated here and now that


there are not, and never can be, any theories that prove demonstratively


that other minds exist, or that I know others? mental states. This is not


what should be aimed at in attempting to solve the problem. As Austin puts


it “To suppose that the question ?How do I know that Tom is angry?? is


meant to mean ?How do I introspect Tom?s feelings?? is simply barking up


the wrong gum-tree.”


Most philosophers agree that their theories only bestow a greater or


lesser amount of probability onto statements about other minds (although


there are exceptions, e.g. Peter Strawson?s attempt to argue


transcendentally for the existence of other minds through our own


self-consciousness). There have been a number of different attempts to do


this. J.S. Mill, who produced the first known formulation of the Other


Minds problem, used the so-called ?Argument from Analogy? both to explain


how we come to believe in other minds and to justify this belief. Briefly,


the argument holds that I am directly aware of mental states in myself,


and I am aware of the behaviour of mine that results from and is caused by


these mental states. As I can observe similar physical behaviour in


others, I draw the analogy that it is caused by the same (or at least


similar) mental states to my own. As in all arguments from analogy, I


assume that because x is similar to y in some respects, it will be similar


in others. So as I know how I behave if I am feeling, say, angry, I assume


in someone else?s case that his behaviour is an indication of the mental


state I call ?anger?. My opinion in this respect is aided by the fact that


most humans? behaviour when they claim to be angry is broadly similar.


The argument from analogy, also employed by Bertrand Russell in a slightly


simplified form, is subject to a devastating criticism. Unlike most


analogies, in the case of other minds, there is no conceivable way of


verifying the conclusion we make. We have no way of discovering whether


someone else is angry or not, and our position means that this is a


necessary disadvantage. The only way to have someone else?s experiences


would to become that person, and in doing that, I would no longer be


myself and I would no longer be having someone else?s experiences. Thus it


is impossible to conceive of any set of experimental circumstances under


which I would be able to ascertain whether or not the human who is


expressing anger-behaviour really is angry or not. And as Norman Malcolm


has pointed out, as there are no conceivable criteria I could use to


determine whether someone is angry or not, simply claiming that they are


angry is a meaningless statement.


Many philosophers, perceiving this fatal flaw in the argument from


analogy, have attempted to produce theories on other minds that are not


based on analogy. Malcolm himself held that the problem lies in the belief


that in looking for evidence of other minds, we need to start off from our


own case and then look for evidence that other cases resemble my own in


other humans. He claimed, characteristically following Wittgenstein, that


statements about mental states in others have no ?special? status but


rather that they are ?primitive, natural expressions? of the state in


question. In other words, ‘my leg hurts’ is equivalent to non-verbal


behavioural expressions of having a painful leg such as crying, limping,


or holding my leg. The statements are not propositions as such, and so


have no ?truth-value?. In my view, there are huge problems with this


account. Firstly, its explanatory power is exceedingly limited as it makes


no distinction between those who are pretending to be in a mental state


and those who genuinely have it. How does it help us to believe that our


world is not populated by robots? Secondly, it does not sufficiently


explain how we came to attach the words we do to our mental states. Crying


and limping are ?natural?, animistic reactions to pain, but language is


learned from others. How can this be accounted for?


Other philosophers have been less successful in escaping the clutches of


the argument from analogy. H.H. Price, in his article Our Evidence for the


Existence of Other Minds, seems to dismiss it, but then employs it


himself, simply changing the terms of the analogy, claiming that we come


to believe in other minds through other humans? use of informative


language, not through their behaviour.


A.J. Ayer, in his essay One?s Knowledge of Other Minds, argues that the


belief in other minds is at least as justifiable as any other inductive


argument. When we refer to the mental states of others, the descriptive


content of that reference need not necessarily include any reference to


the possessor of that mental state. There is no contradiction in asserting


that I could have had that mental state. Implicit in this argument is


Ayer?s belief that a person is no more than the aggregate of all his


properties. Thus, as none of those properties are necessarily unavailable


to me, I make no contradiction when I say that I could have had them:


“But even if my friend has no properties which make him an exception to


the rule about feeling pain, may he not still be an exception just as


being the person that he is? And in that case how can the rest of us know


whether or not he really does feel pain? But the answer to this is that


nothing is described by his being the person that he is except the


possession of certain properties. If, per impossible, we could test for


all the properties that he possesses, and found that they did not produce


a counter-example to our general hypothesis about the conditions in which


pain is felt, our knowledge would be in this respect as good as his: there


would be nothing further left for us to discover.” (pp 213-4).


And thus, if I could have had the mental states in question, I could be


the person who had them. And if I could be that person, I could verify


whether that mental state actually exists or not. Ayer?s reasoning seems


valid enough, but it is hard to know precisely what he means.

It seems


certain that in referring to mental states, it is implicit that someone


owns (or is) the mind in which those states are occurring. Although Ayer


is right in his claim that we need not refer to the ?owner? of the state


when we talk about the state itself, and therefore that the owner ?could?


be us, this doesn?t seem to address the issue at hand. The problem is one


of other minds, and we are, all of us, in a situation where we find


ourselves confronted with apparent minds other than our own which are


problematic.


>From the realisation that a belief in other minds can only arise through


observation of the behaviour of others arose the ?cul-de-sac? philosophy


of logical behaviourism. This theory, now largely discredited, holds that


all statements about mental states can be translated, without loss of


meaning, into statements about observable behaviour. Thus to say that


Jones is in pain is to say that (for instance) Jones is wincing, crying


out, grimacing etc. The statements are equivalent, and consequently the


problem of other minds is not so much solved by behaviourists as


dissolved. But the terminal problem for behaviourists lies in the case of


first-person psychological statements. We certainly don?t learn about our


own mental states by observing our own behaviour. When I say ?I have a


headache?, I don?t mean that I am clutching my head, that I am taking


aspirin etc. The feeling of the headache seems in some way to pre-empt all


of this behaviour, and generally to be the primary cause of it. The


behaviourists made a valiant attempt to solve the problem of other minds


by doing away with the asymmetry between my mental states (normally taken


to be learnt through introspection), and the mental states of others


(normally taken to be learnt through introspection), but they ultimately


failed because their account of first-person psychological statements was


utterly inadequate.


Wittgenstein, in his 1953 work Philosophical Investigations, attempted to


show that the construction of a private language (a language that no-one


other than the creator is logically capable of understanding) was


impossible because languages must follow rules, and it would be impossible


for a language with no external reference to follow rules. For instance,


if I have a certain experience x one day and call it ?pain?, and then have


another experience y the next day which happens to be different to the one


I had the day before but which seems to me identical, and so I also call


it ?pain?, how, as far a I am concerned would this situation differ from


one in which the second experience was actually x? It would not, so I


could conceivably be wrong in every statement I make regarding my own


mental states. The point Wittgenstein is trying to bring out is that,


contrary to the philosophies of Cartesianism and traditional empiricism,


the language we couch our mental statements in is a public language: the


words we use only acquire their meaning through public usage. And thus if


there were no other minds in the world other than our own, we could not


make publicly understandable statements about our mental states. This is a


powerful argument, although it is open to at least two criticisms.


Firstly, it is claimed by some philosophers that it leads inexorably to a


form of behaviourism in which my knowledge of my own mental states through


introspection is not accounted for. Secondly, the argument tells us very


little about the content of other minds. What is the relation between


words and mental states?, and more importantly, how could it conceivably


be discovered? By appeal to our own case? That would just beg the


question.


Nevertheless, I believe that Wittgenstein?s approach is the correct one.


It is a truism to say that I cannot have your experiences, and it always


remains logically possible that an malin g?nie has set me amongst a world


of unthinking, unfeeling robots who have been programmed to exhibit


behaviour (both verbal and non-verbal) leading me to assume that they have


thoughts and feelings. But this seems somewhat unlikely. Rather, it seems


more sensible to believe that there are minds animating all the beings


around me. If I am not to be subject to the sorts of criticisms that


Malcolm makes of the argument from analogy, then I must define some sort


of criteria for asserting that Mr X is feeling y etc. And my only


criteria, of course, can be my observations of his behaviour. To ensure


that my interpretations are as accurate as can be, I must take into


account everything about him: his simple overt behaviour, his environment


and social context, his biological make-up etc. And my reference point can


only be myself, as I am the only example in the world of whose mental


states I can be confident. So as far as X?s circumstances and behaviour


mirror my own, I can say that his mental states mirror mine. And I can go


slightly further: I can claim that my knowledge of my own case can give me


an idea of how certain properties and the connections between them can


affect mental states, and so if I notice some property x in X that happens


not to belong to me but of which its significance concerning mental states


I am aware, then I can make statements regarding X?s mental states with a


certain confidence. If this conclusion seems rather weak, then I can only


appeal to the enigmatic nature of the problem itself and ask others to


better it.


Finally, I would like to mention an observation of mine regarding the


nature of the problem itself. The problem of other minds arises because we


have no certain criteria for ascertaining the possessing of a mind (or


mental states) by a being, and this in turn arises because we do not know


precisely what a mind is. If philosophers of mind ever produce a theory of


mind which provides us with knowledge, to a certain extent, of the nature


of mind, then it would at least theoretically be possible to have criteria


for the possessing of mind, which would provide very good foundations for


the solving of the problem of other minds.


Bibliography


Sartre by Arthur C. Danto. Fontana, 1975.


Strawson?s Transcendental Deduction of Other Minds by J.L. Martin in New Essays in


the Philosophy of Mind ed. John-King Farlow and Roger A. Shiner. Canadian


Association for Publishing in Philosophy, 1975.


The Philosophy of Sartre by Mary Warnock. Hutchinson & co., 1965.


Analogy by Bertrand Russell in Essays on Other Minds ed. Thomas O. Buford.


University of Illinois Press, 1970.


Our Evidence for the Existence of Other Minds by H.H. Price in Essays on Other


Minds.


Wittgenstein?s Philosophical Investigations by Norman Malcolm in Essays on Other


Minds.


Knowledge of Other Minds by Norman Malcolm in Essays on Other Minds.


Other Minds by J.L. Austin in Austin?s Philosophical Papers ed. J.O. Urmson and G.J.


Warnock. Clarendon Press, 1979.


One?s Knowledge of Other Minds by A.J. Ayer in Philosophical Essays by Ayer.


Macmillan and co., 1953.


The Mind and its Place in Nature by C.D. Broad. London, 1925.


The Concept of Mind by Gilbert Ryle. London, 1949.


The Oxford Companion to Philosophy ed. Ted Honderich. Oxford, 1995.


31b

Сохранить в соц. сетях:
Обсуждение:
comments powered by Disqus

Название реферата: Other Minds Essay Research Paper The problem

Слов:2681
Символов:17274
Размер:33.74 Кб.