РефератыИностранный языкFeFeminist Ethics Essay Research Paper 113099

Feminist Ethics Essay Research Paper 113099

Feminist Ethics Essay, Research Paper


11-30-99 Feminist Ethics is not a special ethic in the manor that business,


medical, or environmental ethics are. Feminist ethics have not attempted to


determine special rules for special circumstances, rather they present the


opportunity to examine a historically neglected perspective when it comes to


traditional ethical thought. Feminist Ethics has been an attempt to revise,


reformulate, or rethink those aspects of traditional western ethics that have


historically depreciated or devalued a women’s moral experience, and a women?s


perspective on ethical thought. Among others, feminist philosopher Alison


Jaggar has faulted traditional western ethics for failing women in five related


ways. First, she argues that it shows little concern for women’s as opposed to


men’s interests and rights. Second, it dismisses as morally uninteresting the


problems that arise in the so-called private world, the realm in which women


cook, clean, and care for the young, the old, and the sick. Third, it suggests


that, on the average, women are not as morally developed as men. Fourth, it


overvalues culturally masculine traits like independence, autonomy, separation,


mind, reason, culture, transcendence, war, and death, and undervalues


culturally feminine traits like interdependence, community, connection, body,


emotion, nature, immanence, peace, and life. Fifth, and finally, it favours


culturally masculine ways of moral reasoning that emphases rules, universality,


and impartiality over culturally feminine ways of moral reasoning that emphasise


relationships, particularity, and partiality.[1]


In essence Jagger is pointing out what has been wrong with traditional ethical


thought. While it is convenient to call this feminist ethics, the term is


problematic in that it implies that there are masculine ethic?s. These are


arguably those ethical thoughts which are biased and centred on the idea of a


patriarchal world, or wrong as that old joke says about anything that comes out


of a man?s mouth. However there is a plethora of thought that is not biased and


has been spoken by men, so what is its label? For the same reason I would say


that there is a wide range of thought that women produce and can produce that


should not be labelled ?feminine? and be sidelined as some feminist thought is


for that reason. For the purpose of this paper I am going to accept the term


?Feminist ethic?s? and use it, since it is an answer to what has been wrong


with the study of ethics in general, namely the lack of a feminist point of


view, and if that is to be termed feminist ethics, so be it. It is possible to


argue that the overall aim of most all feminist approaches to ethics,


irrespective of their specific labels, is to create a gender-equal ethics, a


moral theory that generates non-sexist moral principles, policies, and


practices, and it is from this position that I am going to address the issue. Feminist


approaches to ethics, as well as debates about the allegedly gendered nature of


morality, are not contemporary developments. A variety of eighteenth and


nineteenth-century thinkers? discussed


what is probably best termed "women’s morality." Each of these


thinkers pondered questions such as: Are women’s psychological feminine traits


all natural? Or is it only women’s positive


psychological feminine traits that are natural, their negative ones being somehow socially-constructed? Is there a gender


neutral standard available to separate women’s good or positive traits from


women’s bad or negative traits? As it seems to be an underlying argument that


some men?s patriarchal traits are negative. Can it not be argued that traits


which are moral virtues as well as psychological traits are connected with


one’s affective as well as cognitive dimensions, indeed with one’s physiology


as Aristotle and Aquinas suggested, shouldn’t we expect men and women to manifest


different moral virtues as well as different psychological traits? Should all


individuals be urged to cultivate precisely the same set of psychological


traits and moral virtues, or should there be room for trait and virtue


specialisation, provided that this specialisation is not split specifically


down gender lines? Or even if this specialisation is split down gender lines?


Is that a negative, or positive idea? When it comes to


the questions about "women’s morality" that have been posed above,


the eighteenth-century thinker Mary Wollstonecraft answered that women’s and


men’s moralities are fundamentally the same. Although she did not use the term


"socially-constructed gender roles," Wollstonecraft refuted the


concept that women are by nature more pleasure seeking than men.


She reasoned that if men were confined to the same societal rules and roles


women find themselves locked into, as is the case with low-ranking military


men, for example, they would develop the same kind of weak characters women


have traditionally developed within these roles. Denied the chance to develop


their rational powers, to become moral persons who have concerns, causes, and


commitments over and beyond their own physical and psychological pleasure, men


as well as women would become overly "emotional." [2] Wollstonecraft believed in the distinction between manners and


morals, morals with lead to ethics and manners which are a societal training on


the right way to act within a situation. Manners do not require a subscription


to the moral belief behind them, only that you follow them. Morals require


educated thought to arrive at them and know why you have them, whereas manners


are simply something that you are taught to do and can be mastered by any one.


Historically society has taught men morals, and it teaches women manners. More


specifically, society encourages women to cultivate negative psychological


traits like "cunning," "vanity," and


"immaturity," all of which impede the development of more positive psychological


traits. Even worse, society twists what could be woman’s genuine virtue into


vices. Wollstonecraft specifically claimed that when strong women practice


gentleness, it is a grand, even godly, virtue; but when weak women practice it,


it is a demeaning, even subhuman, vice. ?"when it is the


submissive demeanour of dependence, the support of weakness that loves, because


it wants protection; and is forbearing because it must silently endure


injuries; smiling under the lash at which it dare not snarl" [3] However things had


changed a little by the nineteenth-century, women were regarded as more moral though


they were still considered to be less intellectual. than men, a view that


disturbed the utilitarian philosopher John Stuart Mill. As he saw it virtue along


with intellect had nothing to do with the gender of the subject in question. He


said that society was wrong to set up an ethical double standard when it comes to


assessing ?a women’s morality differently


than it assesses a man’s morality. Mill concluded that women’s "moral


nature" is not the result of innate female propensities but of systematic


social conditioning. To praise women on account of their great


"virtue" is merely to compliment patriarchal society for having


inculcated in women those psychological traits that serve to maintain it. Women


are taught to live for and sacrifice for others; to always give and never


receive; to submit, yield and obey; to be long-suffering. Their


"virt

ue" is not of their own doing; it is something that society


imposes it upon them. [4] Proponents of the feminist


approach to ethics like Carol Gilligan and Nel Noddings have stressed that the traditional


western moral theories, principles, practices, and policies are deficient to


the degree that they ignore, trivialise, or demean those personality traits and


virtues of character that are culturally associated with women. Gilligan has presented


her work as a response to the Freudian notion that whereas men have a


well-developed moral sense, women do not. Freud attributed women’s supposed


moral inferiority to girls’ psychosexual development. Whereas boys break their


attachment to their mothers out of the fear of being castrated by their fathers


if they don’t, girls remain emotionally tied to their mothers since the threat


of castration has no power over them. As a result of this state of affairs,


girls are supposedly much slower than boys to develop a sense of themselves as individual


moral agents who are personally responsible for the consequences of their


actions or inaction?s; as persons who must obey society’s rules or face its


punishments. In a sense this causes men to have to learn morals, while women


are able to just follow the manners that they are taught by their mothers, not


having to develop a set of moral understandings on their own. [5] In order to move


towards a more gender neutral study of ethics Gilligan has begun to study men’s


as well as women’s moral experience, as opposed to just a woman?s. Her central


aim is to expose the ways in which society continues to muffle men?s


sensitivity, encouraging them to be less than caring and fully nurturing human


persons. Gilligan stresses that unlike today’s women who speak the moral


language of justice and rights nearly as fluently as the moral language of care


and relationship, men remain largely unable to express their moral concerns in


anything other than the language of justice and rights, while women have


adapted and shown that they have the same capacity to operate in both spheres


of moral thought men have for the most part remained locked into the same pattern


of moral reasoning. One index of the


importance of Gilligan’s work the number of thinkers who have taken her work


seriously enough to critique it. To date Gilligan’s critics have focused either


on the relationship between justice and care, considered as two, gender-neutral


perspectives on morality, or on the fact, that women are culturally associated


with care and men are culturally associated with justice. Critics who have adopted


the first strategy are primarily non-feminist critics. Some of them argue that


even if care is a moral virtue and not just some pleasant psychological trait


that some people happen to have, it is a less essential moral virtue than


justice is. Among the statements such non feminist critics make is that it is


better to act out of a general moral principle like "aid the needy"


than a particular caring feeling, because principles are more reliable and less


ephemeral than feelings; and that, when justice and care conflict,


considerations of impartiality must overcome considerations of partiality: my


children’s fundamental rights and basic needs are neither more nor less


important than anyone else’s children’s, as opposed to the natural way that


most parents would weigh their children?s needs as more important then the


needs of other children. The concept of viewing all children as equal including


your own is much easier when ones emotions are not allowed into the debate. Or


when you are debating from a purely clinical point of view. The one question and


problem to this though is, is the tendency to view your own children?s needs as


more important, simply a issue of ?care? and therefor not within the male realm


of ?justice? for most fathers when faced with the same dilemma would have the


same reaction as any mother. Their children?s needs are more important then the


needs of others. To say that this view is essentially a feminist or feminine


ethic is to ignore the reaction of most fathers. This calls to question whether


or not this aspect of the ?ethics of care? is a trait that can be labelled


feminine, or is it one of the traits that can be considered gender neutral. Feminist Ethics offers to women multiple standards that validate a woman’s


different moral experiences in ways that point to the weaknesses as well as the


strengths of the values and virtues that culture has put the label of ?feminine?


on. ?In addition, they suggest to women


several paths, all of which lead toward the one goal that is essential to the


project of any women-centred ethics; namely, the elimination of gender


inequality. Although


feminists’ have different interpretations of what constitutes a voluntary and


intentional choice, an improper or legitimate exercise of control, and a


healthy or unhealthy relationship reassure the intellectual and moral community


that, after all, for the most part feminism and most feminists are trying not


to be an ideology that prescribes that there is one and only one way for all women to be. ?However this variety of thought is also the


occasion of considerable political fragmentation among feminists. Asked to come


to the policy table to express the


feminist perspective on a moral issue, all that an honest feminist ethicist can


say is that there is no such


perspective. Yet, if feminists have no clear, and unified position on a key


moral issue, then a perspective less appealing to women may fill the gap.


Although it is crucial for feminist ethicists to emphasise, for example, how a


policy that benefits one group of women might at the same time harm another


group of women, it is probably a mistake for feminist ethicists to leave the


policy table without suggesting policies that are able to serve the most important interests of the widest range of women. In the light of


the important contributions made by feminists by the way of theories,


perspectives and attention that has been given to issues. Feminist theory has


been beneficial in the field of ethics not only in opening up discourse, but


offering alternative theories. In this way Feminist ethic?s has been beneficial


to the field of ethics. Given the underlying questioning nature of Feminist


ethics, it is a very beneficial avenue of philosophical inquiry, given that a


questioning nature and analysis and discourse are important aspects of


philosophy. Bibliography Daly, Lois K. (ed.) (1994) Feminist


Theological Ethics. Louisville, Kentucky. Westminster John Knox PressGilligan, C. (1982). In a Different Voice:


Psychological Theory and Women?s Development. Cambrige, Mass.: Harvard University


Press.Jagger, A.M. (1983) Feminist Politics


and Human Nature. Totowa, NJ.: Allenheld.Jagger, A.M. (1991) Feminist ethics:


Projects, problems, prospects. In C. Card (ed) Feminist Ethics. (Lawrence,


Kan.: University Press of Kansas).Mill, J.S. (1970) The Subjegction of Women.


In A.S. Rossi (ed), Essays on Sex Equality. Chicago: University of Chicago


Press. Walker, Margaret U. (1998) Moral Understandings:


A Feminist study in Ethics. New York. Routledge. Wollstonecraft, M. (1988). A Vindication


of the Rights of Women, ed. M.Brody. (London: Penguin.) [1] (Jaggar, "Feminist Ethics," 1992). [2] (Wollstonecraft, A Vindication of the Rights of Women,


1988). [3] (Wollstonecraft, A Vindication of the Rights of Women, p.


117). [4] (J.S. Mill, The Subjection of Women, 1970). [5] (Gilligan, In a Different Voice, 1982).

Сохранить в соц. сетях:
Обсуждение:
comments powered by Disqus

Название реферата: Feminist Ethics Essay Research Paper 113099

Слов:2584
Символов:17793
Размер:34.75 Кб.