РефератыИностранный языкGeGender Bias Essay Research Paper Both men

Gender Bias Essay Research Paper Both men

Gender Bias Essay, Research Paper


Both men and woman have intentions and act, so both are capable of


virtue. Virtue ethics as a theory of morality has existed, most


notably, since Aristotle. Courage is one such virtue and to display


this persons need to experience fear and perceive danger. The


circumstances surrounding an act of courage need to be proportionate to


perceived risk to avoid the activity becoming an enterprise of


foolishness. Also the potential costs associated with the risk must be


proportionate to the ends concerning the bravery. These elements


associated with courage are undoubtedly equally available to both sexes


and in the sense of equality feminism woman can and have been


courageous. However, in light of difference feminism, another facet


may need to be added to the modern meaning of courage, as an


acknowledgement that virtues are characterised with respect to


attitudes held within the context of definition.


A virtue is a prescription of how someone should be. It is a


component of character. Aristotle (cited in Hinman, 1998, pp.


334-335), described virtue as being a mean, or average of attitude


which could be uncovered via reasoning and displayed through


personality and behaviour styles. For example, the average between an


excess like contrariness and a deficiency like sycophancy might be


honest opinion.


Hinman mentions further the difference between substantive virtues,


those that are closer to the ethical good, like philanthropy, and


executive virtues those less associated with being morally good and


more directly linked with qualities of desirable persona. Courage is


said to be an executive virtue (Ibid., p. 336).


The virtue of courage contains at least two components. First there


must be an internal factor of fear or even phobia. Psychology tells


us that fear is an awareness of physiological changes in response to


some stimulus or other. These changes include increased respiration,


heart-beat, blood-pressure, and higher production of epinephrine


(adrenaline). Other changes such as pupil dilation, increased sweating


and decreased production of saliva are often present too. This process


occurs in a part of the autonomic, non-voluntary, nervous system called


the sympathetic division (Aitkenson, Atkinson, & Hilgard, 1983 p.


331). All healthy humans, male or female have sympathetic divisions of


the autonomic nervous system and are thus prone to the physiological,


and thus the psychological, experience of fear.


Second, there must be an external factor of perceived danger in a


circumstance for a courageous deed to be possible. The degree of such


will depend on how the individual relates the present circumstance with


experiences of past events and situations. For example, if I see a


torrentially flooded river an attempt to cross it would be perceived as


dangerous because I have seen many such situations on television where


lives have been put at risk. This cognitive component is important in


danger because I may enter a dangerous situation without realising it


and thus act without courage. It could be imagined that an individual


has no idea that, to get a culled animal for feeding their family, they


may have to walk across a minefield. If the minefield is unknown to


the individual then no fear will be experienced because no danger is


attached to collecting the prey on the other side of the field. So in


this case no act of bravery has been committed. Alternatively, it


appears! courage can be displayed without any real danger existing.


Phobias have the component of fear without physical danger. A phobia


may be defined as an irrational fear, associated with a stimulus


containing no objective hazard. To confront a phobia takes similar


courage needed in non-phobic situations because the associated


behaviours necessary to conquer the phobia are manifested despite fear


or anxiety.


This is contrary to Hinman’s concept of rightly ordered fears. He


maintains that once phobias have been overcome courage is no longer


part of the relationship between actor and situation. He also


maintains that if courage is responding to objectively identifiable


danger then responses to psychological dangers will not count and if


individuals do not perceive objective dangers as such they will not be


counted as courageous. This all appears acceptable. However, Hinman


then seems to discount facing phobias as a valid form of courage


(1998; p. 338).


Phobias may be placed in the objective realm of rightly ordered fears


because for the phobic actor, no matter how illogical the response is


to the stimulus, all elements of fear and danger still exist. The


proportion of fear to actual risk to an unempathetic observer, may be


unbalanced. But because fear is a subjective emotion, it seems


illogical to try and objectively quantify, or comparatively ordinate it


with dangers that are also subjectively assessed by the phobic. All of


this infers that courage is more attached to overcoming fear rather


than danger. Indeed, the dangerousness of a situation is often out of


the actor’s control. However, fear is not always a controllable


phenomena either, and this is perhaps why when people act against


perceived danger, in spite of fear, they are considered courageous


(Hinman, 1998; p. 338). Again it appears that most healthy, rational


humans, woman and men alike, are capable of recognising dangerous


situations with the relevant knowled! ge in tow. Both men and woman


also confront phobias, and so in these respects courage does not appear


to be a gender specific virtue.


There must also be appropriate self-confidence and a relatively


accurate assessment of the risk involved in any action for it to be


courageous, rather than foolish. To skydive without training would be


risky. A person who partook in such an activity without worrying


about the likely consequences, would be quite foolish. However, the


same act carried out by someone who is properly trained can be seen as


moderately courageous, at least for the first few times. Once more


skill and experience is gained the less fear is likely to be


experienced. Indeed, the physiological components once associated with


fear may be associated with an experience of exhilaration.


Sensibility, is also a factor in courage. It would also be foolish to


do something like risk one^s life for the sake of something like a TV,


because the risk involved, when compared with the outcome, is just not


worth it. But, to risk life or injury for the sake of another human


being would not be so foolish because!


the intended ends justify the possible cost (Hinman, p. 339).


As all of the above appears to be equally applicable to both men and


woman it seems almost inane to ask whether or not courage is a gender


specific virtue. But the context of the question needs to be


illustrated. For Aristotle the virtue of courage is associated with


actions of soldiers in battle and soldiers in the armies of his times


were all men. Also acts of courage exhibited by woman have tended to


be under-valued, or even unrecognised (Hinman, p. 341).


The above modern framing of the concept of courage is far wider than


Aristotle’s and woman are generally more accepted as equals to men now,


and this is why it is safe to say courage is not gender-specific.


Courage is not just something which can be displayed in battle, it can


be displayed in any risky situation. For example, many woman become


pregnant without the means material and or psychological to cope with


such. Much pressure is experienced by woman who abort as a result of


their immediate circumstances. Not only is there huge moral debate


about the act of abortion, which must increase trauma, but the


procedure is hugely stressful physically and psychologically. Surely,


courage is needed to make decisions in circumstances such as these. The


act of giving birth is also one which requires great courage.


Historically, this ordeal was extremely risky because of crude medical


technology as Hinman recognises (1998; pp. 341-342). Now, birth is


still a very painful proce! ss and in order to have a child woman are


still at risk of complications associated with such. Woman also


partake in military roles traditionally exclusive to men. The Red Army


contained female regiments, some modern Muslim armies contain female


regiments also, woman fighter pilots are part of some modern airforces


and, the Royal New Zealand Navy, amongst others, employs woman on its


warships. M any police forces and fire departments have woman assigned


to front-line duty. Courage is now equally available to woman, in


consideration of this, even if the Aristotelian definition of such is


adhered to. Maybe now woman, becaus

e of the sex roles they partook in


historically, require another facet to be added to the definition of


courage. This addition may make the acts of courage exhibited by woman


more obvious.


The implications of how to act in order to display the virtue of


courage appear to lean towards male sex role stereotypes. The


stereotypes have been displayed over centuries by men who have been


socialised accordingly. Now in the late 20th century, in order to


attain gender equality, it seems as if females have to display


courageous behaviours according to how men have defined them, rather


than modifying how one should act in order to manifest such.


Historically, it appears that Hinman^s definition of courage is


applicable to how men have been defining and displaying courage. It


may be argued that the traditional role of woman in the family and


society is one that has been directed by men resulting in the


suppression of real female freedom and ability, and thus female


oppression.


Socialisation is perhaps the reason why female emancipation, to the


extent it exists now, did not occur until the 1960s. This seems


reasonable to assume, because if woman are as courageous as men,


according to the overcoming of fear in the face of danger definition,


equality should have been achieved long before it was. But it was not


until late last century, and in this century, that considerations such


as; females obtaining equal voting rights, having control over foetal


conception, and the confirmation of potential equality in the workplace


through mass employment mobilisation in the two World Wars, that


notions of gender equality were seriously considered by large numbers


of the female populace. All of this ascribes to the notion of ^equality


feminism^, where female equality is associated with having the same


opportunities and aspirations as men (Gilligan, cited in Hinman, 1998;


p. 383).


However, the notion of ^difference feminism^ recognises that females


see the world differently, and this may implicate, that virtues will be


manifested within them in ways other than defined to date (Ibid.). In


psychologist Carol Gilligan^s view, woman^s morality focuses primarily


on caring, emotionality, and responsibility (Hinman, 1998; pp.


375-377). With reference to Hinman^s discussion of Gilligan^s stages of


woman^s moral development, courage could be seen as maintaining a


responsibility for oneself and others, despite circumstances of duress


and hardship. Continuing to live one^s life as a responsible and


caring agent, in spite of oppression, and making the most out of the


resources available whilst being oppressed, might be seen as a form of


female courage in history. In contemporary times, however, the female


voice will be extended from within, to the outside world, for the


purpose of recognition as a valid point of view in spite of discounting


attitudes (Ibid. p. 3! 84).


Brown and Gilligan^s qualitative research (1992, cited in Hinman,


1998; p.342), concerning the hardship experienced in the female voyage


from adolescence to adulthood leans towards this idea and is consistent


with Gilligan^s conception of ^difference feminism^. The courage


described, appears to be less of facing a concrete danger, and more of


a self determined endurance concerning the righteousness of emotional,


intra-personal, and interpersonal attitudes and actions. Despite


apparent external pressure to the contrary, caring for oneself, and


taking responsibility for acknowledging the validity of this


developmental process had high priority in these young woman^s lives.


Importantly, these internalised conflicting mind sets were allowed by


the younger woman, to be voiced publicly. Older woman interviewed,


appeared to be less forthcoming, more restrained, and self-censored in


voicing opinions pertaining to similar experiences in woman-hood. The


research implied the censo! rship and subjective perception of


relevance of the personal voice was due to changing patterns in


socialisation rather than attitudinal differences developed through the


life-span (Reimer, 1996).


MacIntyre (cited in Csongradi, 1996), proposes that virtues are based


on sources, gathered through historical perspectives, allowing society


to retrospect and then endeavour to find standards of excellence based


on such. These standards encourage individuals to behave according to


moral perspectives found in areas such as in popular culture. Thus,


different genders could have very different thoughts about what is an


issue of courage and, also have different perspectives on how to deal


with such issues. This para-evolutionary approach appears to be


congruent with the Brown and Gilligan study mentioned above. An example


of this is the present notion of ^girl-power^ in youth culture. Due to


influences of bands such as The Spice Girls, traditionally downplayed


aspects of personality like acute-femininity are being acknowledged as


being as powerful and as sound as personality expressions associated


with acute-masculinity. Naturally, the band is heavily marketed, but


still their image gives credence to this point. The Spice Girls are


unashamedly all-female, dress according to youth culture, and


underline their stance with lyrics, consistently reinforcing the


relevance of the young female reality, such as in the song ^One of


These Girls^ (Furguson, 1998). Other bands like The All Saints, and


New Zealand^s own Mary, follow along similar lines.


The discussion above highlights the relevance of Hinman^s plurality


ethics (Hinman, 1998; pp. 35-36). He bases his pluralism on four


principles. First, is a principal of understanding. Through a sincere


desire to comprehend variance, we must effort to embrace different


expressions of virtues regarding how such are defined by cultures and


sub-cultures. Second, by acceptance of the validity of different


manifestations of courage as a virtue in different sexes, diversity in


such can be recognised and Hinman^s principal of tolerance will be


accommodated. Although, tolerance appears to have a slightly negative


connotation in that it implies an attitude of putting up with


something. Here, a principle of acknowledgement is possibly more


appropriate. Third, acceptance of multiplicity in the expression of


courage endorses its non-gender specific nature. Because courage is a


virtue, validating diversity in the expression of such will likely


reinforce its proliferation and, wil! l apply to the principal of


standing up against evil, and perhaps help extinguish the vice of


cowardice. Fourth, in the above discussion, Hinman^s principle of


fallibility is also relevant because, regarding Gilligan^s difference


feminism, it has been the implication that a traditional male


conception of the dangerousness aspect in courage may be subtly lacking


in points of emotion and responsibility. Importantly, the realisation


of this emotional facet in perception of danger, will validify not only


difference feminism, but also related experiences faced by men. Today,


although perhaps to a decreasing extent, we live in a society wherein


emotionality as a part of how men experience fear and danger, and thus


display courage, is inclined to be discounted too.


In conclusion, it is apparent that courage is not a gender-specific


virtue. In all aspects, for courage to be expressed, males and females


appear to be equally equipped. Both sexes experience fear and are


capable of assessing dangerous situations, accurately or erroneously.


Both sexes are involved in roles which regularly necessitate courage.


These observations are aligned with the idea of equity feminism.


However, recently recognised facets of the female intra-personal and


inter-personal experience adds greater dimensionality to how courage


may be identified and expressed by woman. Consequently, the


existing framework surrounding criteria for what is an act or


pre-disposition for courage may have to be modified. This point is


reinforced by moral attitudes apparent in contemporary culture and, is


congruent with Gilligan’s notion of difference feminism and Hinman’s


ethics of plurality.


REFERENCES


Aitkenson, R. L., Atkinson, R. C., & Hilgard, E. R., (1983). Introduction to Psychology (8th Ed.) San Diego; Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich.


Csongradi, C., (1996). Why the Topic of Bioethics in Science Classes? http://www.gene.com/ae/21st/SER/BE/index.html


Furguson, G. M., (1998). The Spice Girls Space. http://www.geocities.com/Hollywood/Hills/8699/oneof.html


Hinman, L.., (1998). Ethics (2nd Ed.). San Diego. Harcourt Brace College Publishers.


Reimer, S., (1996). In the Works of the Bard Woman Find True Voices. http://www.sunspot.net/columnists/data/reimer/0721reimer.shtml


——————————————————————————–

Сохранить в соц. сетях:
Обсуждение:
comments powered by Disqus

Название реферата: Gender Bias Essay Research Paper Both men

Слов:2969
Символов:21027
Размер:41.07 Кб.