The Fundamental Theorem Of Algebra Essay, Research Paper
The Fundamental Theorem of Algebra states that every polynomial equation of degree n with complex coefficients has n roots in the complex numbers. In fact, there are many equivalent formulations: for example that every real polynomial can be expressed as the product of real linear and real quadratic factors.
Early studies of equations by al’Khwarizmi (c 800) only allowed positive real roots and the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra was not relevant. Cardan was the first to realize that one could work with quantities more general than the real numbers. This discovery was made in the course of studying a formula which gave the roots of a cubic equation. The formula when applied to the equation x = 15x + 4 gave an answer getting -121, yet, Cardan knew that the equation had x = 4 as a solution. He was able to manipulate with his “complex numbers” to obtain the right answer yet he in no way understood his own math.
Bombelli, in his Algebra , published in 1572, was to produce a proper set of rules for manipulating these “complex numbers”. Descartes in 1637 says that one can “imagine” for every equation of degree n, n roots but these imagined roots do not correspond to any real quantity.
Viete gave equations of degree n with n roots but the first claim that there are always n solutions was made by a Flemish mathematician Albert Girard in 1629 in L’invention en algebre . However he does not assert that solutions are of the form a + bi, a, b real, so allows the possibility that solutions come from a larger number field than C. In fact this was to become the whole problem of the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra for many years since mathematicians accepted Albert Girard’s assertion as self-evident. They believed that a polynomial equation of degree n must have n roots, the problem was, they believed, to show that these roots were of the form
a + bi, a, b real.
Now, Harriot knew that a polynomial which vanishes at t has a root x – t but this did not become well known until stated by Descartes in 1637 in La geometrie , so Albert Girard did not have much of the background to understand the problem properly.
A “proof” that the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra was false was given by Leibniz in 1702 when he stated that x + t could never be written as a product of two real quadratic factors. His mistake came in not realizing that i could be written in the form a + bi, a, b real.
Euler, in a 1742 correspondence with Nicolaus(II) Bernoulli and Goldbach, showed that the Leibniz counterexample was false.
D’Alembert in 1746 made the first serious attempt at a proof of the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra. For a polynomial f he takes a real b, c so that f(b) = c. Now he shows that there are complex numbers z and w so that
|z| < |c|, |w| < |c|.
He then states the process to converge on a zero of f. His proof has several weaknesses. First, he uses a lemma without proof which was proved in 1851 by Puiseau, but whose proof uses the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra. Secondly, he did not have the necessary knowledge to use a compact argument to give the final emphasis. Despite this, the ideas in this proof are important. Euler was soon able to prove that every real polynomial of degree n, n 6 had exactly n complex roots. In 1749 he attempted a proof of the general case, so he tried to proof the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra for Real Polynomials:
Every polynomial of the nth degree with real coefficients has precisely n zeros in C.
His proof in Recherches sur les racines imaginaires des equations is based on decomposing a monic polynomial of degree 2 into the product of two monic polynomials of degree m = 2. Then since an arbitrary polynomial can be converted to a monic polynomial by multiplying by ax? for some k the theorem would follow by iterating the decomposition. Now Euler knew a fact which went back to Cardan in Ars Magna, or earlier, that a transformation could be applied to remove the second largest degree term of a polynomial. Therefore, he assumed that
x + Ax + Bx +…
=(x + tx + gx + …)(x – tx + hx + …)
and then multiplied and compared coefficients. Euler claimed to g led to h, … being rational functions of A, B, …, t. All this was carried out in detail for n = 4, but the general case is only a sketch.
In 1772 Lagrange raised objections to Euler’s proof. He stated that Euler’s rational functions could lead to 0/0. Lagrange used his knowledge of permutations of roots to fill all the gaps in Euler’s proof except that he was still assuming that the polynomial equation of degree n must have n roots of some kind so he could work with them and deduce properties, like eventually that they had the form a + bi, a, b real.
Laplace, in 1795, tried to prove the Fundamental Theor
Gauss is usually credited with the first proof of the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra. In his doctoral thesis of 1799 he presented his first proof and also his objections to the other proofs. He is undoubtedly the first to spot the fundamental flaw in the earlier proofs, namely the fact that they were assuming the existence of roots and then trying to deduce properties of them. Of Euler’s proof Gauss says
“… if one carries out operations with these impossible roots, as though they really existed, and says for example, the sum of all roots of the equation x+ax+bx+.” = 0 is equal to -a even though some of them may be impossible (which really means: even if some are non-existent and therefore missing), then I can only say that I thoroughly disapprove of this type of argument.
Gauss himself does not claim to give the first proper proof. He merely calls his proof new but says, for example of d’Alembert’s proof, that despite his objections a rigorous proof could be constructed on the same basis. Gauss’s proof of 1799 is topological in nature and has some rather serious gaps. It does not meet our present day standards required for a rigorous proof. In 1814 the Swiss accountant Jean Robert Argand published a proof of the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra which may be the simplest of all the proofs. His proof is based on d’Alembert’s 1746 idea. Argand had already sketched the idea in a paper published two years earlier Essai sur une maniere de representer les quantities imaginaires dans les constructions geometriques . In this paper he interpreted i as a rotation of the plane through 90 so giving rise to the Argand plane or Argand diagram as a geometrical representation of complex numbers. Now in the later paper Reflexions sur la nouvelle theorie d’analyse Argand simplifies d’Alembert’s idea using a general theorem on the existence of a minimum of a continuous function.
In 1820 Cauchy was to devote a whole chapter of Cours d’analyse to Argand’s proof. This proof only fails to be rigorous because the general concept of a lower bound had not been developed at that time. The Argand proof was to attain fame when it was given by Chrystal in his Algebra textbook in 1886. Chrystal’s book was very influential.
Two years after Argand’s proof appeared Gauss published in 1816 a second proof of the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra. Gauss uses Euler’s approach but instead of operating with roots which may not exist, Gauss operates with indeterminates. This proof is complete and correct.
A third proof by Gauss also in 1816 is, like the first, topological in nature. Gauss introduced in 1831 the term ‘complex number’. The term ‘conjugate’ had been introduced by Cauchy in 1821.
Gauss’s criticisms of the Lagrange-Laplace proofs did not seem to find immediate favor in France. Lagrange’s 1808 2nd Edition of his treatise on equations makes no mention of Gauss’s new proof or criticisms. Even the 1828 Edition, edited by Poinsot, still expresses complete satisfaction with the Lagrange-Laplace proofs and no mention of the Gauss criticisms.
In 1849 (on the 50th anniversary of his first proof) Gauss produced the first proof that a polynomial equation of degree n with complex coefficients has n complex roots. The proof is similar to the first proof given by Gauss. However it is adds little since it is straightforward to deduce the result for complex coefficients from the result about polynomials with real coefficients.
It was in searching for such generalizations of the complex numbers that Hamilton discovered the quaternions around 1843, but of course the quaternions are not a commutative system. The first proof that the only commutative algebraic field containing R was given by Weierstrass in his lectures of 1863. It was published in Hankel’s book Theorie der complexen Zahlensysteme .
Of course the proofs described above all become valid once one has the modern result that there is a splitting field for every polynomial. Frobenius, at the celebrations in Basle for the bicentenary of Euler’s birth said:-
Euler gave the most algebraic of the proofs of the existence of the roots of an equation, the one which is based on the proposition that every real equation of odd degree has a real root. I regard it as unjust to ascribe this proof exclusively to Gauss, who merely added the finishing touches.
The Argand proof is only an existence proof and it does not in any way allow the roots to be constructed. Weierstrass noted in 1859 made a start towards a constructive proof but it was not until 1940 that a constructive variant of the Argand proof was given by H. Kneser. This proof was further simplified in 1981 by M. Kneser, H. Kneser’s son.